Etikk i
praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2024), 18(2), 11-21
|
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v18i2.6193 |
First publication date: 27 December 2024 |
Vilhjálmur Árnason’s Call for Expanding Bioethical Discourse: “The Personal is Political”
Margit Sutrop
University of Tartu,
margit.sutrop@ut.ee
This
article explores Vilhjálmur Árnason’s
critique of contemporary bioethics,
particularly its limited focus on
individualistic principles, and its neglect
of the broader social implications of
emerging technologies. Vilhjálmur argues
that the commonly used “four principles
approach”—respect for autonomy, beneficence,
non-maleficence, and justice—is inadequate
for addressing the complex ethical and
societal impacts of new technologies. He
suggests that ethical evaluations must
extend beyond immediate individual risks to
consider broader societal consequences. Keywords: bioethics, personalized
medicine, genetic database, four-principles
approach, principlism, pluralism, value,
ethical theory, personal is political,
socio-political context Introduction Icelandic
philosopher Vilhjálmur argues that ethical
evaluations grounded solely in individual
virtues or personal interests fall short of
capturing the full scope of moral
responsibility. Moreover, he contends that a
holistic understanding of morality must
encompass broader social and political
dimensions. His perspective, inspired by
ethical choices in Icelandic sagas and applied
to contemporary bioethical discussions,
suggests that assessment of issues such as
population genetic research, personalized
medicine, surrogacy, and organ donation
requires a broader ethical framework. Central
to Vilhjálmur’s thesis is the view that
individual moral agency is inherently
interwoven with the socio-political context,
thus encouraging a comprehensive analysis of
the ethical implications of actions and
policies. In
critiquing overly individual-centered
bioethical frameworks, Vilhjálmur raises a
critical theoretical question: what kind of
ethical theory does bioethics truly require?
He argues (2012: 107) that the four principles
approach widely used in bioethics—respect for
autonomy, beneficence, non-maleficence, and
justice—is insufficient to address the complex
ethical and social impacts of emerging
technologies. The ethical assessment of such
innovations, he suggests, should go beyond the
immediate risks to individuals and consider
their broader societal consequences. The Importance of Social
Context in Ethical Analysis Vilhjálmur’s
exploration of Icelandic sagas (1991) provides
a unique perspective on morality, revealing
that the sagas’ morality cannot be fully
understood without acknowledging their social
roots. He critiques traditional
interpretations of saga morality, such as the
romantic and humanistic views, as overly
focused on personal attributes and qualities.
Instead, he advocates for a sociological
interpretation, asserting that moral actions
within the sagas reflect the social structures
that shape and define individual behavior.
Vilhjálmur states: The
morality of the sagas is analyzed primarily in
terms of personal qualities and attitudes. The
physical and moral strength that enabled
individuals to fulfill their duty of vengeance
is the main criterion by which their
characters are measured (1991: 158). Here,
the individual’s actions cannot be evaluated
independently of social expectations and
collective values, illustrating how personal
virtues and societal obligations are
interconnected. In his article “The Personal
is Political: Ethics and Personalized
Medicine” (2012), Vilhjálmur critiques the
individualistic focus in personalized
medicine, arguing that this approach risks
eroding the solidaristic foundation of
healthcare by placing undue responsibility on
individuals and overlooking the
socio-political conditions that affect health
outcomes. He argues that personalized medicine
can disadvantage specific populations and
challenge the healthcare system. Vilhjálmur
acknowledges the blurred line between
bioethics and biopolitics, as the former
engages questions about the ideal healthcare
system and the kind of society we aspire to
create.
Vilhjálmur’s
Approach to Embedding Ethical Analysis of
New Technologies in Social and Political
Context In
his programmatic article “The Personal is
Political: Ethics and Personalized Medicine”
(2012), Vilhjálmur argues that the primary
task of bioethics, metaphorically speaking, is
to keep the “car” from veering off the road to
prevent harm to people. He identifies three
main human interests that four bioethical
principles must protect: an interest in
welfare (to provide benefit and prevent harm),
an interest in self-determination (to protect
the conditions of agency), and an interest in
fair co-existence (to ensure justice,
fairness, or solidarity). His main thesis is:
“Bioethical evaluation of emerging
technologies certainly must take these
interests into account. This does not mean,
however, that bioethical analysis is limited
to these principles.” (Vilhjálmur 2012: 106) What
Vilhjálmur finds as missing is the social and
political context surrounding
emerging technologies. In his view, a
bioethical framework must encompass broader
social and political dimensions, urging a
shift beyond the narrow, individualistic scope
that often characterizes traditional
bioethics. This expanded perspective
emphasizes collective welfare and societal
impacts, advocating for a form of bioethics
that is as concerned with preserving the
social fabric as it is with safeguarding
individual rights. However,
Vilhjálmur does not explicitly specify how
this context should be integrated into the
evaluations of the ethical and social
implications of projects like personalized
medicine. Instead, his subsequent discussion
of personalized medicine centers on four key
principles, which he prioritizes and organizes
according to their relevance and potential
conflicts. In this article (2012), Vilhjálmur
notes that a primary aim of personalized
medicine is to benefit patients (through
targeted therapy) as well as society (by
reducing healthcare costs). The principle of
beneficence is closely associated with the
principle of non-maleficence (“do no harm”) if
personalized medicine can reduce adverse drug
reactions and improve safety. At the same
time, he acknowledges that personalized
medicine introduces at least three risks.
First, there is a concern about justice if the
pharmaceutical industry lacks incentives to
develop treatments for so-called “orphan
populations”. Second, pharmacogenetic testing
may also reveal disease risks, potentially
infringing on individuals’ autonomy and
privacy and causing harm. Third, there is a
risk to patient privacy and data
confidentiality, as the benefits of
pharmacogenetic testing require sharing
information with a broader group of healthcare
providers. Autonomy,
a key value, is explored from multiple
perspectives. The bioethical principle of
autonomy protects the patient’s agency—their
freedom to make independent decisions and to
act freely. Autonomy includes the freedom to
choose whether to undergo genetic testing and
the right to decide whether they want to know
their genetic susceptibility. However,
effective decision-making requires being
informed, having accurate information, and
understanding it. Vilhjálmur emphasizes that
veracity is a prerequisite for autonomy. He
argues that autonomy in this context extends
beyond informed consent; it encompasses the
right to evaluate whether benefits are
distributed equitably. Vilhjálmur
acknowledges that he prioritizes the principle
of justice (encompassing fairness and
solidarity) above others. In his discussion of
justice, Vilhjálmur highlights the social
dimensions that underlie this principle. For
instance, the principle of justice protects a
collective interest in fair co-existence,
which is especially relevant in addressing
issues related to orphan diseases. Here,
Vilhjálmur references John Rawls’s (1974)
widely accepted principle of justice, which
asserts that an unequal distribution of social
goods is justifiable only if it benefits the
least advantaged. Vilhjálmur argues that this
principle aligns closely with the principle of
solidarity, as it reflects a commitment to
upholding fair social conditions and a shared
responsibility for sustaining them. Through
this interpretation, Vilhjálmur frames justice
in terms of solidarity, underscoring that no
one should be unfairly privileged or
marginalized. He suggests that individual
rights are anchored in mutual respect.
Vilhjálmur clearly states that […]
the principle of solidarity is of major
importance in the discussion of health and
genetics due to the emphasis on protecting
weaker groups in society and ensuring the fair
distribution of healthcare services (2012:
112). He
further notes that the principle of solidarity
underpins many European healthcare systems,
especially those in Nordic countries. This
position firmly aligns him with a political
value—equality—which frequently conflicts with
the individual interest in personal welfare
(beneficence). In
this way, Vilhjálmur’s emphasis on societal
consequences introduces a political dimension
to ethics. By advocating for the
prioritization of solidarity, Vilhjálmur
clearly argues for the primacy of this value
over others, illustrating that ethical
assessments must consider not only medical or
physical harm but also the handling of
personal information in ways that respect
social equity (2012: 110). At
the same time, he treads on slippery ground,
as solidarity is precisely the kind of value
whose universality has been questioned.
Finnish bioethicist Matti Häyry (2003) has
observed that solidarity is a rich concept
with several distinct meanings. He explains
that […]
solidarity, in its non-liberal and
non-utilitarian meaning, was introduced to
ethics by Christian thinkers, who in the early
twentieth century invented the doctrines of
“solidarism” and “personalism,” according to
which individuals and societies cannot be
sharply distinguished as they are “thrown to
each other” (Häyry 2003: 206–207). In
bioethics, Häyry acknowledges, solidarity is
often portrayed as the European counterpart to
justice, representing a more caring and
relational approach to addressing the human
condition, in contrast to the cold and
calculating liberal notion of justice.
Similarly, American philosopher Robert Baker
has argued that the concept of solidarity is
distinctly European, rooted in the cultural
tradition of the French Revolution, and that
“the concept of solidarité
has no resonance” in North America and much of
Asia (Baker 2005: 194). Principlism’s Neutrality to
Ethical Theories Is Vilhjálmur’s approach truly in
conflict with principlism or the
four-principles approach to biomedical ethics?
Beauchamp and Childress’s framework
anticipates the need for context and
prioritization. Their approach is built on two
core assumptions: first, the presupposition of
a common morality, which implies the existence
of universal moral norms binding on anyone who
adheres to morality; and second, the plurality
of principles—respect for autonomy,
beneficence, non-maleficence, and justice.
These principles are intended to be specified
and balanced using the method of reflective
equilibrium. As described by its proponent
John Rawls (1971), reflective equilibrium
requires us to consider a wide range of
principles, arguments, and theories, revising
them until a coherent agreement or equilibrium
is achieved. Specification adds
context-specific content to the principles,
while balancing assigns relative weight to
conflicting principles in specific cases. Beauchamp and Childress have
stated, In
the process of specifying and balancing norms
and in making particular judgments, we often
must take into account factual beliefs about
the world, cultural expectations, judgments of
likely outcomes, and precedents to help assign
relative weights to rules, principles, and
theories (2009: 370). What is notably missing from this
list is an ethical theory, political ideology,
or theory of value. This omission is
intentional; in Principles of Biomedical
Ethics, Beauchamp and Childress avoid
grounding their approach in any single ethical
theory. They explain: ‘Ethical
theory’ and ‘moral theory’ are commonly used
to refer to each of the following: (1)
abstract moral reflection and argument, (2)
systematic presentation of the basic
components of ethics, (3) an integral body of
moral principles, and (4) a systematic
justification of moral principles. We have
attempted in this book to construct a coherent
body of virtues, principles, and rules for
biomedical ethics only. We do not claim to
have developed a comprehensive ethical theory
in ways suggested by the combination of (3)
and (4). We engage in theory (e.g., in
evaluating other ethical theories), and in
doing so we engage in abstract reflection and
argument (2). But, at most, we present only
elements of a comprehensive general theory
(2009: 333). Beauchamp and Childress’s aim is
to provide a flexible, broadly applicable
framework that can be embraced by people with
diverse ethical, cultural, and ideological
backgrounds. By not committing to a specific
ethical theory—such as utilitarianism,
deontology, or virtue ethics—they make the
framework adaptable to different moral
perspectives. This flexibility facilitates
consensus in bioethics, establishing a common
ground for varied viewpoints to coexist
without being limited by rigid theoretical
constraints. By avoiding alignment with a
specific political ideology, Beauchamp and
Childress also maintain a focus on universally
relevant principles, ensuring the framework’s
applicability across diverse social and
political systems. Their approach thus remains
neutral and adaptable, grounded in shared
moral intuitions rather than in specific
theoretical or political commitments. This neutrality is meant to
prioritize practicality and inclusivity over
theoretical rigor. While this is advantageous
for broad application, it also exposes
principlism to criticisms, such as those
raised by Vilhjálmur (2012), about its
limitations in addressing complex social and
political dimensions in bioethics or by
Matthew Shea (2020), who argues that since
both specification and balancing necessarily
involve an appeal to human goods and evils,
they cannot be carried out without a theory of
the good. I align with Shea’s view that
Beauchamp and Childress rely on an implicit
value theory in their own analysis of
bioethical cases, thereby confirming that
axiological considerations are doing essential
normative work in balancing judgements.
However, I think that these procedures of
principlism’s pluralistic
approach—specification and balancing of
principles—also require a conception of
morality. While the four principles outline
the norms biomedicine should follow based on
shared morality, they leave significant
interpretive flexibility to bioethicists.
These principles can be specified and balanced
through Rawls’s (1971) celebrated account of
“reflective equilibrium,” but guidance on how
to contextualize and prioritize norms when
they conflict is underdeveloped. Deciding
which principle should prevail in a specific
context, or which is paramount in cases of
conflict, arguably requires a more robust
ethical theory explaining why certain actions
are morally good or justifiable. Tom L. Beauchamp explicitly
denies the necessity of grounding bioethics in
philosophical theory, stating that many
individuals in law, theological ethics,
political theory, the social and behavioral
sciences, and the health professions carefully
address mainstream issues of bioethics without
finding ethical theory helpful for their
analysis (Beauchamp 2004: 209). Beauchamp and
Childress provocatively argue: Reasons
exist, then, for holding that moral theory is
an important enterprise, but that distinctions
among types of theory are not as significant
for practical ethics as some seem to
think. It is a mistake to suppose that a
series of continental divides separates moral
theorists into distinct and hostile groups who
reach different practical conclusions and fail
to converge on principles. Many theorists are
closer in substantive principles and rules to
allegedly rival theories than they are to some
theories of their own “type” (2009: 363). Why Moral Disagreements are
Unavoidable? When proponents of various
theories describe an action as “morally good,”
they may refer to distinct aspects: the
character of the actor, the motive, the
consequence, or the action itself.
Consequentialists focus on outcomes,
deontologists on the moral worth of actions,
and virtue ethicists on the actor's character.
This difference in focus is also evident in
the language used by different moral
theories—terms like right or wrong, good or
bad, virtuous or vicious. These differences
arise from a clash in foundational principles. Moral theories differ on
which motivating reasons they provide for
moral actions. For example, although both the
consequentialist and the deontologist may
respond to the value of honesty by
exemplifying it in their life and actions,
her/his reasons for doing so are different.
Such different reasons for action may
sometimes lead to moral disagreements about
what one ought to do. While honoring a value
is also a way of promoting it, devoting
oneself to fostering a value may mean focusing
only on preventing more lies being told
without thereby promoting truthfulness (one
may be allowed to lie to reduce lies in the
world). In addition, it may involve promoting
truthfulness in one’s own life, that is, a
disposition not to lie. I have argued previously
(Sutrop 2020) that many moral disagreements
can be seen as deep conceptual disagreements
arising from fundamental value clashes and
differing concepts of morality. While these
disagreements may not always be resolvable,
understanding why they exist and why argument
alone cannot settle them is crucial. Through
understanding, consensus or compromise may
emerge by considering alternative
perspectives. As pointed out by Thomas
Nagel (1979), disagreements on value-based
questions are natural, as values arise from
fundamentally different sources, creating
incommensurable claims and conflicts shaped by
individual, relational, impersonal, or ideal
perspectives. Nagel identifies five
fundamental value types that lead to basic
conflict: (1) specific obligations to others
or institutions, (2) constraints derived from
universal rights, (3) considerations of
benefit and harm for all sentient beings
(utility), (4) the intrinsic value of certain
achievements or creations, and (5) commitment
to personal projects (Nagel 1979: 130). He
notes that these values constantly shape
everyday decisions, often creating conflicts
both between and within them. Although
attempts have been made to resolve these
conflicts by ranking values or prioritizing
certain perspectives, Nagel argues that such
efforts cannot fully succeed. Values are
rooted in different sources, creating
inherently incommensurable claims. Conflicts
emerge because these sources represent
fundamentally distinct
perspectives—individual, relational,
impersonal, or ideal—all of which are integral
to the human experience. Consequently, moral
conflicts arise from the tension between this
fragmentation of values and the need for
unified decisions. Nagel highlights an
essential insight: by distinguishing between
different types of values, he connects them to
various motivating reasons for moral action,
which can easily lead to moral conflicts,
dilemmas, and disagreements. The differences
in values cannot be ignored if we want to
understand why there are irreconcilable
disagreements in bioethics. Moral conflicts arise in
theories involving multiple principles. While
the pluralists acknowledge the existence of
apparent conflicts due to the
incommensurability of values, monistic
theories—such as utilitarianism and
Kantianism—claim that these conflicts are not
genuine and can be resolved through an
ultimate principle. In one-person moral
conflicts, it is often assumed that a rational
agent can minimize or resolve conflicts within
their personal values. However, Williams
challenges this, viewing conflicts of values
as expressions of a complex inheritance from
diverse social sources, which may once have
been conflicts between societies or historical
states (Williams 1981: 72–73). For Williams,
interpersonal conflicts reflect similar
clashes of values from different origins,
countering the assumption that each party
holds a harmonious set of beliefs that can
resolve the conflict rationally. Alasdair
MacIntyre (1984) similarly argues that ethical
disagreements stem from inherited fragments of
heterogeneous moral theories rooted in
distinct social contexts, making harmony
between them unattainable. Also, Isaiah Berlin argued
that some of the moral and political
disagreements are irresolvable as they are
about different identities and incompatible
human goals. In his famous essay Two
Concepts of Liberty (1958/2002), Isaiah
Berlin argued that the freedom to choose
between ultimate values makes us human. Value
conflicts are frequent because we want to
realize incompatible human goals. Politics and
political theory have been invented because of
men’s disagreements about the ends of life. In
The Pursuit of the Ideal (1947/2013),
Berlin explains that values can clash; they
can be incompatible between cultures or within
the same culture. For one person, justice may
be the only value while for another,
compassion and caring may be just as
important, while not setting justice aside.
Both liberty and equality are important
values, but […]
total liberty for wolves is death to the
lambs, total liberty of the powerful, the
gifted, is not compatible with the rights to a
decent existence of the weak and the less
gifted (Berlin 1947/2013: 12–13). “The Personal is Political” Having
acknowledged that clashes in values are
unavoidable, we return to the claim that “the
personal is political.” Rooted in feminist
theory, this concept emphasizes the connection
between individual experience and broader
sociopolitical structures, highlighting how
personal issues often reflect and are shaped
by systemic power dynamics. In bioethics, this
notion suggests that individual health
decisions and moral judgments are inseparable
from the surrounding sociopolitical landscape.
Vilhjalmur incorporates this idea into his
approach to new technologies, arguing that
ethical judgments must consider social
context. He proposes that moral agency,
particularly in healthcare ethics, is
inherently tied to broader social conditions,
thereby broadening bioethical discussions
beyond the realm of individual autonomy. Vilhjálmur’s
assertion that the personal is political
offers a productive framework for navigating
complex ethical challenges in bioethics. While
bioethics ideally aims for neutrality, it is
often shaped by contributors’ diverse views on
the good life, as well as their political and
religious beliefs. Many ethicists occupy dual
roles as both academics and activists, which
can blur the lines between activism and
academia, the personal and the political, and
the public and the private. One of
the most compelling discussions on whether
academic work and activism can or should
remain separate comes from Tom Shakespeare
(2019), who reflects on his experiences in
disability bioethics and the challenges of
maintaining this distinction. He argues that
when the personal becomes political, the
boundary between academia and activism may
blur: If you are spending your
working ours thinking through oppression and
resistance to it, you are not likely to be
someone who never joins a protest, never
writes a letter of complaint, never organizes
for a better world, let alone be someone who
lives an inequitable or exploitative live. To
do less would be hypocrisy (Shakespeare 2018:
914). Bioethicists
bring different values, personal beliefs,
ideologies, and cultural backgrounds to their
work. For instance, a bioethicist with strong
religious convictions might recognize how
these beliefs could shape their views on
issues like euthanasia, stem cell research, or
prenatal diagnosis. Similarly, one who values
individual autonomy over communal welfare—or
vice versa—may argue for personalized medicine
and pharmacogenomics. A bioethicist aware of a
particular ideological or religious stance
should disclose it to help readers understand
how these views may influence their
conclusions. Similarly,
a bioethicist with a strong commitment to
individual freedoms might clarify their stance
on autonomy and privacy, providing crucial
context for their analysis. Conversely,
someone who prioritizes equality over
individual freedom should acknowledge that
their argument—that the social benefits of a
particular biomedical development outweigh
individual privacy risks—stems from their
ideological perspective. Conclusions Vilhjalmur’s
work bridges personal and political domains in
bioethics, advocating for a perspective that
considers individual ethical agency within the
broader socio-political framework. By
challenging the primacy of individual autonomy
in favor of a more socially integrated
approach, his philosophy urges bioethicists to
evaluate health and moral decisions within
their political and social contexts.
Vilhjálmur also strongly advocates for
society’s responsibility to engage in public
deliberation on the implications of new
technologies, actively shaping policy
decisions related to scientific advancements.
Accepting that the personal is political
suggests that bioethicists, too, should
recognize and reflect on their own biases and
contexts. Vilhjálmur’s
thorough analysis of new technologies and
biomedical projects, such as genetic databases
and personalized medicine, highlights the need
for further specification and hierarchical
balancing of the four principles. Through his
interpretations of autonomy and the relative
importance of solidarity over individual
welfare, Vilhjálmur demonstrates how values,
ethical theory, and worldview interact in
ethical decision-making, revealing his belief
that society often holds greater moral weight
than the individual. His focus on solidarity
and viewing individuals as active citizens
engaged in public deliberation calls for a
more communitarian turn in bioethics.
Notes 1
In Iceland, the surname – Árnason – is
a patronymic and a description rather
than a name. Icelanders use and are
known by their given name. This
practice is followed throughout this
article and Vilhjálmur Árnason will be
referred to as Vilhjálmur when citing
his works. References Baker, Rob
(2005). International Bioethics and Human
Rights: Reflections on a Proposed
Universal Declaration on Bioethics and
Human Rights, Politics and Ethics
Review, 1(2),
188-196. CrossRef Beauchamp, Tom
L. (2004). Does Ethical Theory Have a
Future in Bioethics? Journal of Law,
Medicine & Ethics, 32(2),
209–217.
CrossRef Beauchamp, Tom
L. and James F. Childress (2009). Principles
of Biomedical Ethics. 6th ed. New
York and Oxford: Oxford University Press. Berlin, Isaiah
(1947/2013). The Pursuit of the Ideal. In
Henry Hardy, ed. The
Crooked Timber of Humanity: Chapters in
the History of Ideas, Princeton and
Oxford: Princeton University Press. Berlin, Isaiah
(1958/2002). Two Concepts of Liberty. In
Henry Hardy, ed. Liberty.
Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. Häyry, Matti
(2003). European Values in Bioethics: Why,
What and How to Be Used? Theoretical
Medicine, 24(3): 199-214. CrossRef MacIntyre,
Alasdair (1984). After Virtue: A Study
in Moral Theory. 2nd ed. London:
Duckworth. Nagel, Thomas
(1979). The Fragmentation of Value. In his
Mortal
questions. Ch. 9, 128–141.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rawls, John
(1971). A Theory of Justice.
Cambridge: Harvard Univesity Press. Shakespeare,
Tom (2019). When the Political Becomes
Personal: Reflecting on Disability
Bioethics, Bioethics. Special
Issue: Advocates and Activists, 33(8),
914–921.
CrossRef Shea, Matthew
W. (2020). Principlism’s Balancing Act:
Why the Principles of Biomedical Ethics
Need a Theory of the Good, Journal of
Medicine and Philosophy, 45,
441–470. CrossRef Sutrop, Margit
(2020). Deep conceptual moral
disagreements: Over what do we disagree
and why? Trames. Journal of the
Humanities and Social Sciences, 24(3),
295−314. CrossRef
Vilhjálmur Árnason
(1991). Morality and Social Structure in
the Icelandic Sagas, Journal of
English and German Philology, 90(2),
April, 157–174. Vilhjálmur Árnason
(2005). Dialog und Menschenwürde.
Ethik im Gesundheitswesen. Münster:
LIT Verlag. Vilhjálmur Árnason
(2011). Database Research: Public and
Private Interest, Cambridge Quarterly
of Healthcare Ethics, 20,
563–571. Vilhjálmur Árnason
(2012). The Personal is Political: Ethics
and Personalized Medicine, Ethical
Perspectives, 19(1),
103–122. Williams,
Bernard (1981). Moral Luck.
Philosophical Papers 1973–1980.
Cambridge: Cambridge University
|