Etikk i praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2023), 17(2), 41-52 |
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v17i2.5047 |
Early View publication date:
18 December 2023 |
African Ethics, Personhood,
and War
Luís Cordeiro-Rodrigues
Hunan University, Yuelu
Academy, Department of Philosophy &
University of Lisbon, Centre of Philosophy,
LanCog Lccmr1984@gmail.com
In this
article, I look at the African
theory that the formation of
personhood is relevant to the
morality of war. I start by
justifying the project of
decolonizing the ethics of war.
Then I proceed to clarify that
some of the African theories
that relate to personhood and
war should not be taken at face
value, but that the concept of
personhood does play a role in
the morality of war. I then
provide examples of how this
concept is relevant for jus ad
bellum, jus in bello and jus
post bellum.
Keywords: African Ethics; Personhood; Just War Theory; Jus ad Bellum; Jus in Bello; Jus Post Bellum
Introduction
Some developments have recently emerged that try to globalize the debates in war ethics, using literature on Confucian, Daoist, African, Marxist, Anarchist, Indian, and other philosophical traditions (Cordeiro-Rodrigues and Singh 2019). In this article, I am interested in developing one of these attempts at globalizing the debate, that of African war ethics. The African ethics of war can be found in political, literary, and philosophical writings. Originally, the contemporary arguments about the ethics of war were mostly found in the discourses and theories of African revolutionaries, like Kwame Nkrumah, Nelson Mandela, and Julius Nyerere (Nyerere 1969; Nkrumah 2015; Mandela 1967; Cordeiro-Rodrigues 2022). Recent philosophical work has seen several scholars trying to develop an African just war theory (Metz 2019; Badru 2019; Okeja 2019; Akiode 2019; Cordeiro-Rodrigues 2022; 2018a; Ugwuanyi 2020; Baker 2016; Cordeiro-Rodrigues and Chimakonam 2022). In broad terms, the arguments defended by these scholars have mostly aimed to tease out the implications of ubuntu or concepts related to the ethics of violence. The theory defended in this article does not radically depart from this previous work in the sense that it is also communitarian-driven; but the thesis of this article articulates an African theory of war grounded in a different perspective. Namely, it tries to develop an African ethics of war grounded in the concept of personhood as it is understood in many parts of Africa.
Hence,
it is fair to affirm that African just war
theory is marked by an anti-colonialist tone
and is written from the point of view of the
oppressed: it is a philosophy that emerges
from below. This article is divided into
four sections. In the next section, I
explain the need to decolonize just war
theory. After that, I outline a concept of
African personhood. In section three, I draw
some implications of this African concept of
personhood to jus ad bellum and jus
in bello. In the last section, I
explain the implications of this concept of
African personhood for jus post bellum.
Why Decolonize Just War Theory?
A
preliminary question raised for the purpose
of this paper is why we should decolonize
the ethics of war at all? War
is horrendous. It involves many situations
that challenge the limits of morality (Mcmahan 2011). Indeed, war encompasses
various kinds of behaviour that tend to be
morally wrong: deliberately inflicting
suffering, killing, invading another
country’s territory, deception, and so forth
(Walzer 2006). Most of us have a sense that
these are actions to be avoided at all
costs, if ever morally allowed. Given the
gravity of such practices, they need strong
moral justification (Cordeiro-Rodrigues and Singh
2019). Reasons to enter a war cannot
be trivial: I could not go to war merely
because someone stepped on my foot. Entering
into war needs a strong justification for it
to occur. A strong justification would in
turn be one that appeals to a greater number
of people and uses more resources and
intuitions. Several philosophers, political
scientists, and politicians have, throughout
time, given different kinds of
justifications for the just cause of war.
Most of these justifications have come from
the Western philosophical views operating
within a Christian tradition. For example,
the Medieval and Early Modern philosophers
Hugo Grotius and Saint Augustine have both
written about these topics (Begby, Reichberg, and Syse
2012). Today, the literature is more
diverse, but it still mostly comes from
Western scholarship (Cordeiro-Rodrigues and Singh
2019; Bellamy 2019).
This
reference to the history of Western
philosophy, however, is not enough for a
strong justification. The ethics of war
requires more global responses. The more
global the argument is, the stronger it
becomes. This concern is partly
methodological and partly political.
Methodologically speaking, the more theories
that we compare our views with the more
certain we can be that the theory is a good
one (Sidgwick 1981; Christopher
Simon Wareham 2017; McMahan 2000). A widely-encompassing
discussion will allow us to confront our
arguments through a broad diversity of
views. This is true both for defending an
intuitionist ethical methodology and a
reflective equilibrium. For intuitionists,
to consider the intuitions of non-Westerns
may undermine or strengthen their theory:
the more people share an intuition, the
stronger it becomes, and if other
civilizations do not share the same
intuition, then there are reasons to believe
that the ethical intuition may simply result
from cultural bias. The use of reflective
equilibrium ought to consider a greater
array of theories that may have a good
explanatory power for the normative problems
they are addressing (Rawls 1999); hence, it is also relevant to
consider non-Western along with Western
theories to better judge normative questions
.
Politically
speaking, given that war involves so
many agents, hearing a larger number of
voices seems reasonable in order to
understand the legitimacy of war acts. This
is particularly relevant because African
war ethics hails from the writings of
peoples struggling with oppression and,
as such, their voices are important to
hear. In addition, if war is simply
framed in a Western way, the agents of
war are strategically missing something
important. Note that the Global South is
becoming much more relevant in
international politics. Today, it is not
just immoral but also not possible to
have a Eurocentric conception of world
politics (Agrawal 2023). This means that in
considering international politics, the
relevant agents must consider how the
Global South will position itself.
Clearly, the Ukraine-Russia war suggests
that the European and American
positioning is not all that counts in
assessing what to do. Relevant
stakeholders must decolonize their
approach to war to be able to understand
and accommodate 21st-century
international relations.
An
objection that may arise at this point
is that rather than decolonizing the
ethics of war, we should simply
eliminate war. If war is horrendous, why
can’t we simply render all these
practices morally wrong? After all, if
war involves so many wrongs, it seems
that we could rule out all wars, for all
war is immoral. This pacifist stand,
however, fails for at least two reasons.
On the one hand, it is not realistic.
Wars are a permanent aspect of our
existence and appear to be inevitable. I
do not necessarily mean this in the
sense that we are always in a Thucydides
Trap dynamic. What I mean is that
we live in a world where war is a
constant threat because humans are prone
to conflict, and it is inevitable that
we will have tensions with others. This
is a common view in Western philosophy
and is sometimes called political
realism. As I argue elsewhere, the
African tradition also has elements of
moral and political realism,
understanding conflict and war as an
inevitable aspect of reality
(Cordeiro-Rodrigues and Chimakonam
2022).
This is noticeable in Igbo
philosophy, for example, which routinely
conceives of good and evil as two
aspects of reality simultaneously
present in entities: good and evil
require each other and fuel each other
to exist (Anizoba 2008; Nwonwu 2014;
Mbiti 1990). I would go further and
contend that often, even in pacifist
theologies and philosophies – like that
espoused by Desmond Tutu – some elements
suggest that the world is characterized
by constant tension (Cordeiro-Rodrigues 2018b). At the end of the day,
this idea could be summed up in the way
that Carl
von Clausewitz perceptibly captured
the relevance of war: war is the
continuation of politics by other
means (Clausewitz 1976). Indeed, we are
political animals, so, we also undertake
politics through war.
Taking this on board, to not have an
ethics of war is simply to ignore a
problem. Morality ought to be driven
toward real-life issues and not simply
theorize ideal situations.
African Philosophy and Personhood
The
concept of personhood has been rather
prominent in twentieth-century applied
ethics. Many moral arguments about
abortion, euthanasia, and other important
topics in applied ethics have used the
concept of personhood as the basis for
their debates (Blumenthal-Barby 2023). For example, Peter Singer
uses the concept of personhood to debate
topics such as the morality of infanticide
and the treatment of animals (Singer 2015b; 2015a; 2011) Personhood is also relevant
in African applied ethics, but it has been
understood in a very different way (Molefe 2020). Personhood, in the African
context, is not such an intrinsic quality.
It is routinely understood as something
that is acquired through a complex process
of relations with others and the world
around us (C. S. Wareham 2020).
Ifeanyi
Menkiti is the primary philosopher to have
developed this concept (Menkiti 2018; 1984). According to Menkiti,
personhood consists of a process whereby one
becomes virtuous through positive
interaction with others. That is, through
the right sort of interaction with others
(one that involves solidarity and
identification), one becomes a full person.
It is only possible to become a person by
promoting the right sort of proximity
between oneself and others. What we are and
what we become is ultimately the result of
our relationship with what surrounds us,
especially other humans, but also other
animals and the environment. As Menkiti has
famously pointed out, this is a process that
comes about in stages. In broad terms, the
older one is, the more likely it is that a
person has developed full personhood (Menkiti 2018; Molefe 2020). Indeed, this idea is found in
several African proverbs such as ‘What
an old man can see sitting down, a young
man cannot see even if he climbs the
highest iroko tree.’ As this suggests,
personhood is fundamentally about
character and often the terms are used
in interchangeable ways.
A salient belief
in Africa is that societies need
individuals with personhood for them
to function properly. The main reason
for this is that most morality,
according to this African ethics, is
learned by example. Therefore virtuous
individuals play an essential role in
the moral progress and learning of
their communities (Mbiti
1990; 2015). Elders
are often perceived to have a greater
responsibility in forming the moral
character of society because they are
the ones who have often acquired the
experience and know-how to make
well-judged moral decisions. They are
routinely the moral compass of their
communities (Gyekye
2011).
Moreover, in practice, principles of
morality may be too abstract to
respond to real-life situations. So,
the learning of virtues (i.e., the
development of personhood) is critical
for society to function (Tan 2014;
Bell and Metz 2011). For this
reason, only when a society has people
with developed personhood, will the
society be one that is likely to
engage in moral behaviour.
Personhood and War: Jus ad
Bellum and Jus in Bello
|