Etikk i praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2022), 16(1), 1–3 |
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v16i1.4935 |
LederIntroductionFreedom to avoid harm: revisiting some core values that guide moral action
Moral agents have good
reasons to value freedom, including
freedom’s role in making moral agency
possible in the first place. Philosophers
have identified the normative differences
between types of freedom as well as their
differing weights (priorities) with
respect to the potential of such freedom
to significantly harm others. The importance of
prioritizing values by differentiating
types of freedom enables us to apply John
Stuart Mill’s Harm Principle (Brink
2018) not only to freedom of speech (to
which it was originally applied) but also
to other freedoms, such as freedom of
movement during a deadly pandemic. The
ethics of public health and infection
control usually highlights the importance
of limiting the exercise of freedom in the
public sphere only when such freedom
causes harm to the public. “To constitute
a harm, an action must be injurious or set
back important interests of particular
people, interests in which they have
rights [See sections I 12; III 1; IV 3,
10, 12; V 5 in Mill’s Collected Works].”
(Brink 2018) Mill differentiated mere
offense from harm – neither of which is
acceptable – and we have good reasons to
prefer not being exposed to either type of
effect of the exercise of freedom. The
importance of freedom to moral agency is
basic, but we are justified in limiting it
when it harms others. Mill, in fact,
applied this “harm limit” even to freedoms
exercised in non-public relationships,
such as those involving our family (see
for example Brink’s 2018 citing V12 of
Mill’s Collected Works). The state, through legal
means, is the legitimate implementor of
limits to freedom, such as bans on free
speech. However, Mill also weighs the
potential harm of the state’s legal
approach to limiting harmful freedoms. If
limiting freedom for the sake of
preventing harm is more harmful than not
limiting such freedom, he suggests an
alternative intervention that he calls
“general disapprobation” or public
condemnation (Mill as cited in Brink
2018). Mill’s Harm Principle
therefore does not merely restrict freedom
because it causes harm. Because of the
complex nature of harms and freedoms, a
second-order freedom emerges. That
second-order freedom is the freedom to
make a determination about the kinds of
harms we are trying to avoid. That
determination involves weighing the harms
that may result from restricting a freedom
versus the harm that may be caused by
exercising that freedom. Freedom itself, as well as
the different kinds of freedom, are
important. It is also important to
understand that these freedoms are
complex, and that exercising them has
complex effects. That complexity requires
us to bring greater deliberation and
reasoning to applying the other guiding
values behind The Harm Principle.
This activity supplements the main
guidance of this principle that is focused
on preventing harm to others in the
exercise of basic freedoms, such as the
freedom of speech. The
paper by Sigri Gaïni titled Universities
and other Institutions – not Hate Speech
Laws – are a threat to Freedom of
Political Speech, discusses arguments against
hate speech legislation, particularly the
so-called Argument from Political
Speech. According to this argument,
having restrictions on hate speech is
illegitimate in a liberal democracy. The
main reason is because the right to
express oneself freely concerning any
political decision is a core democratic
principle. The author counters this
argument by contrasting the U.S. democracy
to other Western democracies where hate
speech legislation does not seem to
threaten political speech. In the United
States, a country which lacks hate speech
legislation, the real threat to free
speech instead comes from sources outside
the law, such as private institutions like
universities. The reason, according to
Gaïni, is that lack of hate speech
legislation has forced U.S. universities
to require restrictions in their
educational institutions to protect
themselves against hateful speech. The
author concludes that such institutional
restrictions pose the real threat to
freedom of speech. Bouke De Vries,
in the second article, takes on a very
different topic. In Sexist and
Inefficient? The Case for Lowering the
Toilet Seat, De Vries starts out by
observing that many people who pee standing –
who are predominantly male – raise the
toilet seat so that they have a larger
target to aim at. However, if the seat is
left in this position, any subsequent
toilet-user who defecates or pees sitting
down will need to lower the seat. Some
believe that this inconvenience should not
be visited on those who pee sitting down,
while others deny that there is anything
wrong with leaving the toilet seat in the
position that you used it. De Vries offers
the first scholarly defense of the
seat-down norm. In so doing, the author
argues that recent claims that this norm
would be unfair or sexist and inefficient
are unwarranted. In Evidens,
estetikk og etikk: Medisinen i
skjæringspunktet mellom det sanne, det
skjønne og det gode, Bjørn Hofmann
shows how the
field of medicine is a fascinating meeting
place between three classical
philosophical domains: the true (knowledge
and evidence), the good (ethics), and the
beautiful (aesthetics). While modern
thinking has tended to sharply separate
these domains, medicine is defined by
their interconnectedness, according to the
author. Knowledge is connected to pain and
suffering, and beauty to health. The
production of knowledge, he argues, is
directed towards doing good by avoiding
bad. At the same time, medicine is also
governed by aesthetics. The author shows
how a range of challenges follows from the
connection between the three spheres. At
the same time, if we are attentive to
their interconnectedness, writes the
author, medicine becomes a fascinating and
fruitful interaction of truth, goodness,
and beauty. This issue
includes a commentary by Efren Alverio II
titled Revisiting the limits of free
speech on Lavik's ban on climate
denialism. It responds to a
previously published article by affirming
the wrongness of climate denialism (and
other similar dangerous antifactual
sentiments such as COVID-19 pandemic
denialism, anti-vaccine beliefs, etc.).
Alverio II, however, cautions against
making the shift from condemning climate
denialism to banning it altogether. He
argues that due to the vagueness of
standards for reasonableness as well the
demarcation between public and private
(such as religion) domains of speech,
banning climate denialism could cause more
harm than the denialism itself. Ruling
which speech is reasonable or
non-religious, for example, could give
so-called “experts” too much power to
decide which speeches to ban. Allowing
these antifactual sentiments to be out in
the open – despite the risk of being
believed by some people and causing them
to act in potentially harmful ways –
enables them to be exposed and criticized
in a public debate where experts can point
out their fallacies. This issue also includes a
review of David DeGrazia and Joseph
Millum’s 2021 book A Theory of
Bioethics titled Klar for en ny
teori i bioetikk? written by Kamilla
Østerberg og Henrik Wathne. Call for papers on the Ethics of War
Brink, D. (2018). Mill’s Moral and
Political Philosophy. In Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Available at:
https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill-moral-political/#LimLib |