Etikk i
praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2022), 16(1), 5-19 |
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v16i1.4826 |
Early View publication date:
20 June 2022 |
Universities and other
Institutions – not Hate Speech Laws – are a
threat to Freedom of Political Speech
Roskilde University, Department of Communication and Arts and University of the Faroe Islands, Faculty of History and Social Sciences, sigri@ruc.dk One
of
the strongest arguments against
hate speech legislation is the so-called
Argument from Political Speech. This
argument problematizes the restrictions
that might be placed on political
opinions or political critique when
these opinions are expressed in a way
which
can be interpreted as ‘hateful’ towards
minority groups. One of the strongest
free speech scholars opposing hate
speech legislation is Ronald Dworkin,
who
stresses that having restrictions on
hate speech is, in fact, illegitimate in
a
liberal democracy. The right to express
oneself freely concerning any political
decision is, according to Dworkin, a
core democratic principle; it is what
self-governance – and hence liberal
democracies – are built upon. Dworkin
and
many other free speech scholars based in
the United States see hate speech
legislation as a threat to expressing
oneself freely and critically. I argue
that Dworkin and other US-based free
speech scholars tend to overlook actual
hate speech legislation in countries
where such laws have been implemented
and
have functioned for decades.
Furthermore, I argue that the real
threat against
political speech lies not in hate speech
legislation but rather outside of the
law, namely, in private institutions
such as universities and museums.
Restrictions on political speech in
various societal circumstances have been
on
the rise over the last decades – first
and foremost in the US. I analyse why
these restrictions on political speech
are more widespread in the only Western
country without laws against hate speech
than they are in countries with
implemented hate speech laws.
The United States has no laws against hate speech, and hate speech is interpreted as political speech by the court (Sumner 2015). Whether this interpretation is plausible or not is an ongoing debate among scholars. Scholars like Jeremy Waldron and Stephen Heyman argue that hate speech legislation is an important component in liberal democracies, pointing to the fact that the right to be met with equal respect and dignity as a citizen is a basic principle of liberal democracies. Other scholars, like Ronald Dworkin and Thomas Scanlon, argue that limiting hate speech undermines democratic legitimacy, pointing to the necessity for every citizen to have the opportunity to express themselves freely in democratic discussions and stressing that preventing this opportunity undermines democratic legitimacy. Some scholars, including Eric Barendt, explicitly point at expressions of e.g. racial hatred, as falling under political speech (Barendt 2005: 154-155)
1) Hate speech and political
speech are separate matters. Even though
hateful expressions can be classified as
both hate speech and political speech in
certain cases, hate speech as defined by
applicable laws generally is not classified
as political speech. 2) The challenges pertaining to
the limits on political speech are not,
first and foremost, caused by hate speech
laws, but rather, they are caused by other
areas of society than the legislative, such
as university policies.
In the latter part of the paper, I discuss the historical aspects of freedom of speech as well as of what we nowadays call hate speech. Furthermore, I point to the contemporary challenges we are facing with regard to censorship of political speech, in particular at private institutions. I also address the apparent connection between the lack of hate speech legislation in the United States and the demands of restricting (controversial) political speech in private U.S. institutions such as universities.
Attempts
to
explicitly define political speech are
relatively rare (Gelber 2010: 306). Thus,
many scholars refer to political speech
without defining it. However, some scholars
have obviously sought to define the concept
of political speech, e.g. in connection with
their arguments against the passing of hate
speech laws. Cass Sunstein, for example,
defines political speech as speech “both
intended and received as a contribution to
public deliberation about some issue”
(Sunstein 1995: 130), while Eric Barendt
talks about “participation in social and
political deliberation” as well as (and
maybe most importantly) “expressions about
and against the government: verbally
attacking the government” (Barendt 2005:
154-155).
If
weak or unpopular minorities wish to be
protected from economic or legal
discrimination by law – if they wish laws
enacted that prohibit discrimination against
them in employment, for instance – then they
must be willing to tolerate whatever insults
or ridicule people who oppose such
legislation wish to offer to their fellow
voters, because only a community that
permits such insult as part of public debate
may legitimately adopt such laws. If we
expect bigots to accept the verdict of the
majority once the majority has spoken, then
we must permit them to express their bigotry
in the process whose verdict we ask them to
accept. (Dworkin 2006: 87). According
to
Dworkin, the people, as a collective, is
fundamental to the idea of Democracy.
Dworkin looks at liberal democracies as
collective self-governments where citizens
participate in the governing of themselves
as a community – the self-government being a
positive freedom: “the freedom to govern
oneself” (Dworkin 2011: 365).
Dworkin
also
emphasizes the importance of the voices of
minorities. One cannot defend the passing of
laws based on a majority´s will as long as
minorities have not had the opportunity to
protest against these respective laws.
Hence, to Dworkin, the passing of laws
against hate speech would also be a
violation against the voices of those in
minority. It is important to bear in mind
that to Dworkin, the minorities represent
those who are politically in the minority –
and not necessarily minorities characterized
by external factors such as ethnicity, skin
colour or sexual orientation.
We
protect people´s basic dignity because it
matters: it matters to society in general,
inasmuch as society wants to secure its own
democratic order and its character as a
society of equals; and dignity matters of
course to those whose dignity is assaulted.
(Waldron 2014:111). The
difference
in emphasis of democratic values is, in
truth, also a reflection of different
interpretations of democracy itself. One of
the ways to distinguish between these
different interpretations is to
differentiate between the proponents of the
so-called absolutist
position (on freedom of speech) and
the proponents of the balancing
position (on freedom of speech)
(Sunstein 1995). Dworkin
is a representative of the absolutist
position. This approach reflects a
specific view on Liberal Democracy, namely
one in which the Freedom of Speech principle
is viewed as the most important democratic
principle – and one which cannot be
compromised. Waldron, on the other hand, is
a representative of the balancing
position,
which reflects a view of Liberal
Democracy where the various democratic
principles have equal value – something
which means that the principles must
continuously be balanced against each other.
When it comes to hate speech, this balancing
position leads Waldron (and other scholars)
to point to the protection of citizens´
dignity as being more important than the
protection of free speech in general.
Dignity,
on the other hand, is precisely what hate
speech laws are designed to protect – not
dignity in the sense of any particular level
of honor or esteem (or self-esteem), but
dignity in the sense of a person´s basic
entitlement to be regarded as a member of
society in good standing, as someone whose
membership of a minority group does not
disqualify him or her from ordinary social
interaction. That is what hate speech
attacks, and that is what laws suppressing
hate speech aim to protect (Waldron
2014:105). Waldron
stresses
that a democracy shall “secure
its own democratic order and its character
as a society of equals” (Waldron 2014: 111,
emphasis added) – a statement that reflects
the requirement for a democratic government
with respect to fulfilling the task of
ensuring equality among its citizens.
Dworkin, on the other hand, stresses that
partners shall seek to
treat each other with equal
concern and respect, not that the
government shall ensure
that citizens are treated with respect
(Dworkin 2011).
It
is not clear to me that the Europeans are
mistaken when they say that a liberal
democracy must take affirmative
responsibility for protecting the atmosphere
of mutual respect against certain forms of
vicious attack (Waldron 2014: 30). Although
the
argument from political speech is one of the
strongest arguments against the passing of
hate speech laws, there is no indication
that the implemented hate speech laws of
European countries violate the right to
express oneself freely about political
matters in general.
The
problem
with Dworkin´s premise is that there must be
complete
freedom of speech in order to have a
legitimate democracy. Dworkin´s view of the
speech relevant to protect in order to
maintain democratic legitimacy is simply too
broad and his premise about self-government
(and the need for complete freedom of speech
among citizens in order to maintain this) is
unreasonable. Citizens can exercise their
full capacity to perform self-governance
through influencing political
decision-making and the passing of laws even
if they are restricted from expressing hate
speech. One can protest against the passing
of laws and oppose any political
decision-making without having to express
hate speech at all – based on how existing
hate speech laws (e.g. in Europe) are
formulated. Hence, ‘complete freedom of
speech’ is not required in order to actively
participate in self-governance in a liberal
democracy.4
Defining
Political
Speech
I
shall try to define political speech in this
section and argue why hate speech, in my
opinion, cannot be categorized as political
speech in general.
1)
A citizen is
dissatisfied with the many
Middle-Eastern immigrants who have
moved into her neighbourhood lately.
She criticizes the authorities´
decision to allow so many of these
immigrants to move into the
neighbourhood since she finds it to
have a negative impact on the
neighbourhood. The local children
will be influenced by the foreign
children who don´t speak their
language, and the women might feel
threatened by the men when meeting
them alone in the local community,
she reflects. The dissatisfied
citizen posts her thoughts on
Facebook and other social media
where she has a great number of
followers. 2)
Another citizen living
in the same neighbourhood is
likewise dissatisfied with the
authorities´ decision on these
matters. She also decides to post
her opinion on Facebook where she,
as the other citizen, has a large
number of followers. Her post says
that all Middle Eastern men are
terrorists who come to the West with
the sole purpose to kill Western
citizens through terror attacks. According to hate speech
legislation in European (and other)
countries, the second example falls
under the label of hate speech while
the first falls under protected –
and perhaps political – speech. The
second example generalizes and
coarsely degrades Middle Eastern men
(they are grouped based on their
ethnicity) by calling them
terrorists who are on a mission to
kill Western citizens.
The bottom line is that although the argument from political speech is an argument of great relevance and importance in any liberal democracy, its reach does not extend as far as to validate the dismissal of hate speech legislation.
Political
Speech
in a Historical Context and the Problems
of the Absolutist View on Freedom of
Speech
When
the
idea of liberal democracy was developed
during the late 18th century,
freedom of speech was one of the core
principles connected to it. In order to have
a state ruled by the citizens themselves –
to be self-governed – the right to express
oneself was imperative. One cannot be part
of governing a state if one is not free to
express oneself, i.e. to criticize
respective decision-makings, the passing of
laws and the abuse of power. In a liberal
democracy, every citizen shall have the
possibility to gain influence through
expressing themselves freely. These basic
principles are clearly reflected in
Dworkin´s argument from political
speech/democratic legitimacy.
It is interesting that freedom of speech was mostly referred to as freedom of political speech both in ancient Greece as well as during the Enlightenment and subsequent years. Mill, who was one of the most liberal proponents of freedom of speech, focused on “the expression of opinions” with particular concern for “morals, religion, politics, social relations, and the business of life” (Sumner 2015: 27). Hence, it was the expression of opinions on matters such as the above mentioned which were at stake. Personal matters – and personal attacks – were clearly not considered as expressions of opinions.
The
Real
Threat to Political Speech
Political
speech is what the right to freedom of speech
originally addressed: the right to express
one´s opinion about and criticize every
authority, e.g. the church and the government.
With the founding of liberal democracies
followed the principle of self-governance, for
which freedom of speech was a foundational
premise.
I have focused solely on the demands for restricting speech at universities in this paper. I could also have problematized the social media platforms and other types of institutions. Much can be discussed about freedom of speech in relation to the various social media platforms and whether these platforms take enough responsibility when it comes to hateful speech – or whether they, on the contrary, are censoring too much. This is an ongoing and very important contemporary discussion. However, the discussion involves different premises than those concerning restrictions of speech at universities, and hence, I have chosen not to go further into it in this paper.12 Conclusion
Most
proponents
of the argument from political speech hold
that hate speech must be legal in order to
protect the foundation of democracy, namely
self-governance. According to Ronald
Dworkin, restricting any speech at all
delegitimizes liberal democracies by taking
away parts of the people´s possibility to
influence political decision-making and the
passing of laws. I hold that one can be a
proponent of the argument from political
speech while at the same time advocating for
hate speech legislation, since most hate
speech does not fit under the label of
political speech.
Ironically, neither the argument from political speech nor the lack of hate speech legislation has protected political speech in the United States. On the contrary, the lack of hate speech legislation seems to have played a significant part in placing restrictions on political speech in American society in general. The real threat to freedom of political speech is not hate speech legislation – it is the restrictions imposed by private institutions such as American universities. Notes
1 In
Denmark, for example, the law was passed in
1939 on the grounds that anti-semitism had
become a problem (as a result of the ideas
of German Nazism). 2 The
principle of proportionality plays an
important part in the balancing position. It
is not always an easy task to decide what
should be prioritized when, since different
rights and principles of apparently equal
value may in many cases clash. 3 That is
when the First Amendment was adopted, on
December 15, 1791. 4 I base
this on the public political debate in
Europe, which is no less critical of its
governments than the debate in the USA –
perhaps even moreso. 5 There are
many examples of this in numerous newspapers
and other media. Here is one example,
retrieved June 05 2022, from https://www.sandiegouniontribune.
com/opinion/commentary/story/2022-04-10/sdsu-n-word-j-angelo-corlett-academic-freedom 6 This law
concerned merchants and craftsmen (who were
often not citizens). See: Hansen, M.H.
(2010). 7 Results
from a number of studies have shown a
causality between hate speech and hate
crimes, see e.g., Williams, Burnap, Javed,
Liu and Ozlap. (2020) and Eggebø, H. &
Stubberud, E. (2016). 8 There are,
of course, many examples of this to be found
in various media, but there is also one
report from 2021 which documents some of
these issues more specifically, see:
Kaufmann, E. (2021). 9 Steven
Salaita (1975-) is a scholar, public speaker
and a writer. He was born in Buefield, West
Virginia and educated within American
Literature. See e.g.., retrieved June 05,
2022 from https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Steven_Salaita_hiring_
controversy 10 J.K.
Rowling (1965-) is a writer who is mostly
famous for her children´s series Harry
Potter. Rowling was born in Yate,
Gloucestershire. Retrieved June 05 2022
from: https://www.theguardian.com/books/2019/dec/19/jk-rowling-trans-row-court-ruling-twitter-maya-forstater 11 This
refers to the same report mentioned in note
8. References Barendt,
E. (2005). Freedom
of speech, 2nd
ed. Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Dworkin,
R. (2006). The right to ridicule. The
New
York Review. March 23, 2006.
Retrieved June 05, 2022, from https://www.nybooks.com/articles/2006/
03/23/the-right-to-ridicule/ Dworkin, R.
(2011). Justice for
hedgehogs. Cambridge,
Harvard University
Press. CrossRef Eggebø, H., Stubberud, E. (2016).
Hate speech
report 2:
Research on
hate and
discrimination.
Norwegian
Institute for
Social
Research.
Retrieved June
05 200 from https://samfunnsforskning.brage.unit.no/samfunnsfors
kning-xmlui/bitstream/handle/11250/2442453/Report%2B2016_21.pdf?
sequence=2&isAllowed=y Gelber, K. (2010). Freedom of
political
speech, hate
speech and the
argument from
democracy: The
transformative
contribution
of
capabilities
theory. Theory
and Practice
9(3): 304-324.
CrossRef Hansen, M.H. (2010). Demokratiets
historie
– og vores.
København,
Museum
Tusculanums
Forlag Heyman, S. (2008). Free
speech
and human
dignity.
New Haven
& London,
Yale
University
Press Kaufmann, E. (2021). Academic
freedom in
crisis:
Punishment,
political
discrimination,
and
self-censorship.
Centre for the
Study of
Partisanship
and Ideology.
Report No. 2.
Retrieved June
05 2022 from https://cspicenter.org/reports/academicfreedom/ Lægaard,
S.
(2014). Det demokratiske argument for
absolut
ytringsfrihed.
Politik, 17(1), pp. 6-14. CrossRef Mill, J.S. (1859). On
liberty.
London: John
W. Parker and
Son Scanlon,
T.M.
(2003). The
difficulty of
tolerance. Cambridge,
Cambridge
University
Press Sumner, L.W. (2015). The
hateful and
the obscene:
Studies in the
limits of free
expression.
Toronto,
University of
Toronto Press Sunstein, C. (1995). Democracy
and the
problem of
free speech.
New York: The
Free Press Waldron, J. (2014). The
harm in hate
speech.
Cambridge and
London,
Harvard
University
Press Williams,
M.L, Burnap,
P., Javed, A.,
Liu, H. and
Ozlap, S.
(2020) Hate in
the machine:
Anti-black and
anti-muslim
social media
posts as
predictors of
offline
racially and
religiously
aggravated
crime. British
Journal
of Criminology
60(1), 93-117.
CrossRef
|