Etikk i
praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2021), 15(2), 29-47 |
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v15i2.4093 |
The “Foreign” Virus? –
Justifying Norway’s Border Closure
Attila
Tanyia
& Magnus Eganb a UiT The Arctic University of
Norway, attila.tanyi@uit.no b UiT The
Arctic University of Norway,
magnus.egan@uit.no
In response to the COVID
pandemic, the Norwegian government
implemented the strictest border controls
in modern Norwegian history, barring entry
to most foreign nationals. The Prime
Minister, Erna Solberg, justified these
policies with reference to the rise of new
COVID variants and the need to limit
visitors to Norway as much as possible. As
this approach has severe adverse effects
on many people, there is a need to
critically examine the justification given
for closing the border. In this paper, we
argue that while many border restrictions
are legitimate, (1) the arguments given
for the recent banning of entry for groups
of people are not convincing, and (2) that
the ban unduly limits personal freedoms
and places an unjust burden on
transnational citizens and Norwegians with
close relations abroad. Keywords: COVID-19, Border Closure,
Border Restrictions, Justice, Sovereignty,
Nationalism, Immigration, Freedom, Ignorance
Introduction
On 29 January 2021,
the Norwegian government
introduced the strictest entry
rules since March 2020 – which
were the strictest since World
War II. People who did not have
Norwegian citizenship or reside
in Norway would no longer have
access to the country, with a
few exceptions. Most foreign
citizens were denied entry.
These included the following
groups: parents of children over
18, grandparents, adult
children, partners, siblings,
seasonal workers, guest
researchers and students. This
placed a heavy burden on
transnational citizens,1
international migrants who have
attachments and connections in
other countries, and Norwegian
residents who have attachments
abroad. Many were unable to see
their families or start new
jobs, and as the border closure
was open-ended, with no end in
sight, they often found
themselves in an existential
limbo, unable to plan for the
future. In other words, Solberg argued that in order to have quite limited measures in place in Norway, the borders must stay closed. This decision to close the border to most foreigners, and its justification, are the topic of this article. Does the justification by the Norwegian Government stand up to moral scrutiny? And what can we learn from a moral reconstruction of the justification of border closure? The answers to these questions are not trivial and a lot is at stake. While many questions have been asked about the legitimacy of lockdowns,3 fewer questions have been posed about border closures as a pandemic response.4 And though the security of citizens and the protection of basic human rights are often invoked as reasons for states’ right to control borders (Blake 2013, Wellmann 2020), these concerns have to be balanced against the prospective immigrants’ interest in being admitted.5 Many transnational individuals, whose lives occur in more than one country, have seen their lives more severely impacted than others’ over this last year. They not only have to comply with domestic restrictions, but in many cases have not been able to see their loved ones for well over a year. It is therefore of particular importance for the state to offer these individuals solid justification. Thus, it seems reasonable to ask, generally and more concretely in Norway’s case, what justifies border closures in the present pandemic. This is not likely to be the last pandemic we experience in our lifetime, and more countries might seek to employ border closures as new variants spread. With this in mind, it is pressing that we investigate the justification of many of the new policies that have been employed in the last two years and whether they can stand up to moral scrutiny. One caveat before we move on to our argument. It is important to note that we are not questioning the justifiability of border control policies as such as a response to the COVID pandemic. Indeed, requiring quarantine, vaccine certificates and testing on arrival can be seen as directly aimed at controlling the spread of the COVID pandemic, and while there might be issues of proportionality and who should cover their costs, we do not consider these in this paper. We think having requirements for testing and quarantine is reasonable if there is a danger of spreading new variants across borders, or if the level of infections is significantly higher in some countries than others. However, we will consider in more detail the most drastic border control policy, that of partially or fully closing the border.6 To avoid confusion when considering other border control policies, we will refer to them as “border restrictions” in what follows, unless the context explains otherwise. This is how we will proceed: In the next section, we will discuss possible justifications for border closure, some explicitly endorsed by the Norwegian government and some not. Our aim in this section is to morally reconstruct, discuss and refute these arguments. In particular, we consider three approaches that each comprise a bundle of arguments: the ‘imported infection’ argument, the pragmatic argument, and the sovereignty argument. In brief, they argue that border closures are needed in order to limit imported infections, that they are pragmatically justifiable both politically and due to limited knowledge, and that the state has the sovereign right to control who enters its territory. Subsequently, in the third section of the paper, we will put forward arguments against border closure. Here, two strands of argumentation stand out: the argument rooted in freedom, and the justice argument. In short, we argue that the recent measures unjustly limited the freedoms of many individuals, both Norwegians and foreigners, and that they placed not only an unequal, but also an unjust burden on some people. One final admission: We are aware that each of the arguments we discuss could be expanded into a paper in its own right. However, our choice in this paper has been to consider the major arguments one can reconstruct from the public debate and give all of them some consideration. That is, in the paper we are primarily interested in considering and criticizing the various arguments that might support border closures, and we are well aware that much more can be said about many of the issues we discuss. We are willing to sacrifice some depth for the sake achieving more breadth in the argumentation. This does not mean, we hope, that our arguments have no depth, but it does mean that we focus on addressing each of the relevant arguments for border closure and leave a more detailed, thorough discussion of some of the arguments to other papers.
Attempts to
justify border closures in
the ongoing pandemic
As noted, we will
present three arguments in this
section. We will argue that none
of these arguments justify
Norway’s recent border regime
before moving on to consider the
positive case against the
measure in the following
section.
The ‘imported infection’ argument The most commonly cited reason for closing the border for groups of people is to limit the risk of importing infections. Indeed, as mentioned above, one of the most common grounds for justifying immigration control is a government’s need to protect the rights and security of its own citizens (Blake 2013, Wellmann 2020). We will get back to how one might weigh such a right to limit immigration against the rights to free movement towards the end of the article, but first we must assess whether there are good grounds in the case of the pandemic for this commonly cited justification.In governmental press release and other news articles,7 some central claims are repeated: the spread of COVID in Norway is largely due to imported infections, and therefore the borders must be closed so that these infections can no longer enter the country (Office of the Prime Minister(a) 2021) (Fange 2021). In these articles the politicians do not merely want to explain, but also to justify the closing of Norwegian borders to large groups of people. However, what is the justification we are given? As far as we can tell, the reason given for closing borders is that people coming from abroad have brought in the virus. The most common concerns raised against this closure have been the economic consequences and the rather indiscriminate manner of border closure. In particular, the plight of migrant workers and cross-country commuters from Sweden is highlighted. Yet, the basic question is not asked: Why is this fact – that someone coming from abroad might bring in the virus or new variants of the virus – enough to justify not merely increased border restrictions, such as more testing, vaccine requirements and quarantine, but also the closing of borders? Consider the following three points. One, the fact that is appealed to – ‘importing’ infection from abroad – can be cited by every government around the world. After all, outside Wuhan, China, where the virus originated, the rest of the world imported the virus. If everyone followed Norway’s logic, no one from Norway would be able to travel anywhere in the world and no one would be able to travel to Norway. Two, the WHO’s recommendation on international traffic is that “Travel measures that significantly interfere with international traffic may only be justified at the beginning of an outbreak” (World Health Organization 2020 [our italics]; cf. Saxena and others 2021: 4-5). The fact that many countries disregard this recommendation does not make it bad advice. Indeed, its logic is clear: once a virus as infectious as COVID (especially its recent mutant variants) is spreading within a country, the surge in cases will be due to domestic spread and not due to international travel. While it is difficult to disentangle all the effects of various pandemic response policies, both modelling and the limited number of observational studies indicate that this is correct: “Models have found that strict border closures could have helped limit viral transmission in the pandemic’s early days. But once the virus started spreading in other countries, border closures provided little benefit” (Mallapaty 2021). At the same time, undue focus on travel and border restrictions and closures risks hindering effective infection control (Devi 2020). Three, certainly in 2021 the overwhelming majority of infections in Norway, and the spread of new variants, have been due to the domestic spread of the virus.8 It therefore does not seem clear why the mere fact that infection reaches a country from abroad is sufficient, in itself, to justify closing the border to large groups of people. In any case, no perfect closure is possible in our world; even countries as isolated geographically as New Zealand and Australia have not managed to keep the virus out entirely (as evidenced by repeated local lockdowns). So, it is natural to ask why closing the borders is chosen instead of controlling and restricting – via quarantine, testing, isolation – the flow of people through them? Perhaps the WHO recommendation should be handled with more caution, though. One could argue that Norway, when it closed its borders, was in the beginning phase of the pandemic compared to other countries since the infection level had been low, and during the Spring of 2021 the percentage of new variants was low. Yet, based on the publicly available figures it seems clear that Norway experienced both a significant domestic spread of the virus, as well as a significant domestic spread of new variants. In fact, a New Zealand or Australia-type of complete border closure, whereby their own citizens were also denied entry, has never been proposed in Norway. Moreover, most of the virus infections that have been brought into Norway over the last year have come via guest workers and holidaying Norwegians. In order to reduce the spread due to these groups arriving, the government implemented testing and quarantine requirements. And if these measures did not work well enough, that is perhaps due to them not being enforced strongly; not because they are unsuitable for infection control.9 This is clear from the practice of many countries in Europe where borders remained open and only a tiny percentage of infections came from abroad.10 To sum up: We do not think that border restrictions are an ineffective tool in controlling pandemics. This is certainly not the case and research supports this well (Haug, Geyrhofer & Londei 2020; Voigt and others forthcoming). But the question is why border restrictions must take the form of partial or complete border closures. Indeed, border restrictions such as quarantine and testing can be intrusive, but border closures are even more severe measures, both economically as well as socially. Thus, a very strong justification should be given for their introduction – and we have found no such public epidemiological justification. In particular, little justification and debate, grounded on epidemiological projections, have been provided as to why border closures rather than increased testing and quarantine were needed, nor an evaluation of what the impact of the various policy choices might be. In special circumstances, perhaps as in the case of New Zealand and Australia, a suppression strategy that employs complete border closure can be warranted. Perhaps it is, ceteris paribus – though we will argue below that it does not. But Norway has not been, and in 2021 certainly is not, in an even remotely similar situation. Given all the other available forms of border control policies – testing, home quarantine, hotel quarantine, home or hotel isolation – unilateral border closures for foreigners seem to be an unwarranted way of controlling the spread of the virus. At least the Government has not provided an epidemiological justification for why such closures were needed.11
The pragmatic argument One possible reason behind present Norwegian border policy could be political. For some time the parliamentary support for the previous right-wing government was secured by the FrP (The Progress Party), the most nationalistic and anti-immigration mainstream political party in Norway. There might therefore be a temptation to be seen as strict on immigration, particularly since 2021 was an election year.12 However, we are reluctant to take such political considerations as good arguments for border closure. It is hardly relevant for the rightness and wrongness of such a policy, whether or not it promotes the popularity of the government. This might well explain the policy, but it most certainly does not morally justify it.There is, however, another candidate for a pragmatic justification of border closures. In a recent article, Scheall & Crutchfield (2021) argue that their previous work on how policy makers’ ignorance – having to do with their epistemic burdens – influences their choice of policy, can also be applied to COVID measures. “The fundamental problem of politics,” they write, “is that even if policymakers’ motivations align with their constituents’ interests, policymakers may not possess the knowledge necessary to deliberately realize relevant policy objectives.” (Scheall & Crutchfield 2021: 20) This, they argue, applies to policy choice in the circumstances of the pandemic. In particular, they argue that “rather than adopting a focused-protection policy that would have required the identification and isolation of uniquely vulnerable patient populations, policymakers have opted to try to minimize physical suffering due to the virus via the blunt and comparatively simplistic tool of economic and societal lockdown.” (Scheall & Crutchfield 2021: 19) One could – it certainly appears tempting – see border closures in the same light: they are also “blunt and comparatively simplistic” ways of dealing with imported infections. However, what is important to note is once again the difference between explanation and justification. Scheall and Crutchfield acknowledge that their proposal is only meant to accomplish the former task: “Our interest is to explain why certain kinds of policies were chosen and why other kinds of policies were mostly ignored, not to defend any of these policies as either uniquely appropriate to relevant circumstances or morally defensible.” (Scheall & Crutchfield 2021: fn. 6) This, as they argue, is a particularly salient point in later phases of the pandemic, in particular after the Autumn of 2020, as we by then had amassed significant pool of knowledge about both the pandemic and about relevant counter-pandemic policies. In short, policymakers should have learnt which policies are more efficient and which are not in terms of their overall effects, that is, not merely their direct health effects, but also their indirect, social effects. There is, in other words, a difference between ignorance and ignorance. Some ignorance is justified, and perhaps this was true of ignorance at the start of the pandemic (although lack of preparation can still be criticized13). Policymakers could perhaps not help but be epistemically impoverished in the initial phase of the COVID pandemic, and therefore to err on the safe side, be blunt and comparatively simplistic in their policy choices. One might therefore reasonably argue that such a precautionary approach was justifiable, given the lack of knowledge early on in the pandemic. However, the ignorance of the later stages does not appear to be of an excusable kind that could warrant blunt measures like border closures. It would therefore seem to be less legitimate currently to move from explanation to justification of policy choices based on epistemic ignorance. Finally, one could argue that, due to the emergence of new variants, we are continuously in an epistemically impoverished situation. But this does not sound reasonable. Although variants indeed emerge, only very few of them are classified as variants of concern or of interest by the WHO.14 These variants, most recently the dominant delta variant and the now threatening omicron variant, emerge rarely and not entirely unexpectedly (insofar as we know that unless a significant majority of world population is vaccinated, the emergence of variants is likely). This has two important consequences. One, the claim that we are continuously in an epistemically impoverished situation is false. We think the following appears to be a more accurate description: we are moving between long periods of relative epistemic certainty (‘calm’) through short periods of epistemic uncertainty (‘upheaval’). Two, in between these long periods we have ample time to prepare for the emergence of new variants. This is especially so since by now the relevant institutions have developed effective ways of monitoring and studying COVID variants, we have vaccinations and we now also have COVID medications. All in all, what follows from the virus’ tendency to mutate is that there might at most be short periods when border closures are warranted – although we would even doubt that that is the case.15 However, Scheall & Crutchfield (2021), do provide some further explanations as to why politicians seemingly have not learned much from their past mistakes and used their amassed experience. One idea concerns the ‘pretence of knowledge’: policymakers were perhaps ignorant of their own relevant ignorance, which has incentivized them to continue pursuing policies that were not nearly as effective as they have claimed them to be, a fact they would have realized had they acknowledged their earlier ignorance of the matter. A second, according to the authors more relevant proposal is the following: “Past policy decisions affect present and future epistemic burdens. In particular, unless policymakers know how to both alter the chosen policy course and avoid the consequences of acknowledging its ineffectiveness, the alternative of doubling-down on the existing policy is comparatively attractive” (Scheall & Crutchfield 2021: 24). This is basically status quo bias: it is cheaper and easier to continue with present policy, despite evidence to its ineffectiveness, than to change course with all its costs and uncertainties. The political price might be way too much to pay. These are no doubt interesting hypotheses that are worth further elaboration and probing. What is difficult to see is how this might morally justify policy choice. The ignorance we are here dealing with is perhaps rather a form of wilful ignorance: policymakers, driven by their own interests, in both scenarios chose not to do something despite available evidence. And this latter kind of ignorance is hardly justifiable from a moral point of view. Within the
philosophy of migration there
are some debates that are
relevant for the topic under
consideration, in particular
when it comes to various
theories of what justifies a
state’s control over its
borders. The arguments that rely
on collective
self-determination are
particularly pertinent in our
case (Altman & Wellman 2011,
Fine 2013, Miller 2016, Song
2018). These arguments build on
the idea that states need to
control their borders in order
to allow for collective
self-determination. If such
arguments are to justify the
current partial border closures,
they must rely on two
assumptions: First, territorial
states have the right to decide
what happens on their territory,
including border policy. Second,
if they are also democracies,
government policy should follow
the majority view, which could
support border closures during
the present pandemic. Since both
arguments rely on some idea of
popular sovereignty –
understood, roughly, as the
claim that the people are the
ultimate source of political
authority - we call this the sovereignty
argument. Song argues that on the basis of such mechanisms a state’s control over immigration may be justified. However, it seems apparent that several of these mechanisms are not in place in relation to Norway’s recent border closure. First, a series of freedoms are violated by closed borders: freedom of movement, freedom to choose and pursue an occupation – even setting immigrants aside, Norway’s border regime seriously disadvantages guest workers, commuters and members of transnational families.16 Furthermore, the closures impacted the freedom to marry and start a family, not only for cross-border and transnational families, but also for all those whose intimate relationships were not covered by one of the exemptions. Of course, no freedoms are meant to be unlimited, and one can meaningfully discuss where the limits lie in different circumstances, and which freedoms should be given priority. We address this in some detail below. Succinctly put, we do not believe that, especially given existing alternatives, i.e., border restrictions such as quarantining and testing as opposed to border closure, the imposed constraints on these freedoms are justified. As for the second mechanism Song mentions, it is worth differentiating between those who have voting rights and those who do not. Norwegian citizens have direct ways of influencing government policy via periodical national elections. So, at least for them, some level of accountability is established.17 Those who cannot vote are a diverse group ranging from guest workers to permanent residents. Regarding accountability it is also important to mention that the government – and many, if not most, governments in Europe (and the world) – have acquired special powers.18 This significantly reduces accountability. Lastly, the two groups also differ in terms of the forms of dissent available to them. If they break the rules, Norwegian citizens face mainly fines, whereas those who belong to the other group face, potentially, deportation from the country. This difference of burdens resulting from border closure will play a role below in our positive arguments against border closures. The presence of the third mechanism, regarding public rationale, in the COVID pandemic in Norway is also questionable. Of course, the government is closing borders as part of its effort to stop the spread of the virus. This no doubt serves the common good. However, this is only the case when considering the measure in isolation, rather than comparing it to other possible measures – in this case border restrictions that might consist of testing, quarantine, isolation and targeted, short-term closures (towards particular countries and regions with significant outbreaks). And as we have argued above, it is far from obvious that border closure is the superior solution and that it therefore, on the whole, serves the common good. At a minimum, the government would need to provide a public rationale that includes evidence for why border closures, as opposed to border restrictions, are preferable and necessary. Collective self-determination can but need not take a democratic form, though it does so in Norway. So, assuming the majority of the Norwegian public supports border closure, is that not just enough to justify the policy? We do not think that it is. In addition to the above minimal requirements, in the case of democracies, more stringent conditions should be appealed to. Liberal democracies combine the idea of popular sovereignty – taken here to entail some kind of simplified majority rule – with restrictions on the power of the state (such as checks and balances, separation of powers, bill of rights, judicial review and so on). Clearly, border closure, as it has been applied in Norway, infringes on the rights, entitlements and privileges, such as freedom of movement, of many Norwegian citizens and foreign residents. The people affected may be the minority, but in a liberal democracy like Norway they deserve protection. In any case, some special justification would be needed, which has not been provided and which we have not found so far. One could still say that all of the above discussion presupposes one crucial thing: that the political collective in question – the Norwegian political community – does in fact include those whose rights are not respected, for whom proper dissent is not available and to whom the decision-makers are not properly accountable. But is this really so? One could deny this and argue that the Norwegian government does not therefore owe anything to those people whose rights are here being impinged. Yet, the truth of this position is far from clear. At this point it is worth reminding ourselves of exactly who have been impacted by border closures. No doubt many migrants with no ties to the country have been affected. But let us set them aside for now – in this paper our aim is not to argue for a more liberal immigration policy per se. Even so, many more people affected by the policy remain, for whom the present approach is at least questionable. Take Norwegian citizens first. Presumably not even an imaginary objector would doubt that they are part of the relevant collective. The largest group are probably those who are residents but not citizens: EU/EEA citizens, permanent residents, and relevant visa holders. What about them? Exactly how we understand the ‘people’ in question becomes important here. This is another much discussed issue. If one subscribes to a nationalist or some kind of culture-based approach, many individuals who are ‘only’ residents in the country may not belong to the collective. But this is not the only way to conceive of ‘peoplehood.’ As Sarah Fine (2013: 264) points out, “[m]any states are multinational, many national groups cross over the borders of states, and many citizens of many states do not identify with the majority national group in that state.” It is therefore not always easy to define exactly who constitutes the people who are supposed to be self-determining. For example, Song (2018: 396) prefers an account on which “a people comes into being by participating together in ways that express an aspiration to be authors, not merely subjects, of the rules governing collective life.” And the people so construed, on her account, become connected to a particular territory by virtue of its members having a pre-institutional right to occupancy on the given territory. This in turn is grounded in peoples’ stable residency for the pursuit of life projects, claims Song. We cannot pursue this topic further here, but our point is simple: plausible ways exist to constitute the people, connect them to a territory and be part of the collective that do not exclude individuals with stable residence and whose centre of life is in the given place. And these people, however variously constituted, have not been given adequate justification for the border closure.
Based on the above
discussion, we would argue that
the recent Norwegian border
closures are unjustified. Are
there other positive arguments
as to why Norway should try to
avoid such policies in the
future? In the following we
discuss two such arguments: the
freedom argument, which
considers how we should balance
various limits on freedoms, and
the justice argument, wherein we
consider the distribution of
burdens.
The freedom argument
It is clear
that closing borders
violates several freedoms;
hence a natural argument
against border closures
can be made in the name of
protecting our freedoms.
However, this argument is
too simplistic, since it
is also a well-known
dictum that no freedoms
are unlimited. In
particular, freedoms can
clash with each other and
in the process of
adjudication some must
therefore be restricted.
We accept that also in
Norway certain freedoms
can be restricted, and
this applies especially in
the special circumstances
of a global pandemic. We
will consider an approach
to this question using a
broadly Rawlsian
framework.19
The
justice
argument
Our
final argument
against current
border closures
builds on theories
of distributive
justice and
relates to how
burdens are
distributed and
relationships
respected. First,
there is reason to
doubt whether the
distribution of
burdens resulting
from border
closure in
Norwegian society
is just. There is
no question that
the distribution
of burdens is unequal.
What we have said
so far illustrates
this. We are
speaking here of
transnational
families, other
groups with
immigrant
backgrounds,
migrant workers,
foreign students,
and so on. These
people are not
able to do what
other members of
their society can:
travel, meet their
loved ones, spend
time with their
children, or do
their jobs. These
activities are
important,
moreover, as they
are
identity-constituting
and foster basic
relationships,
features and
abilities. Summary and concluding
remarks
The choice to close
the borders or keep them open is
a question of values; it is a
moral choice. In order for the
choice to be justified, it must
not merely be explained
pragmatically or politically but
also have a valid moral
explanation. What are the values
that merit this policy choice?
Even if border closures, as
opposed to rigorous border
restrictions like quarantining
and testing, limit the spread of
the virus, what justifies the
choice that avoiding any
increase in infections trumps
all other values, such as
freedom of movement?
Furthermore, why should foreign
travel be radically restricted
in order to travel freely
domestically and have less
strict pandemic measures? What
justifies this choice?
So far, we have found no
satisfactory moral justification
for the closing of borders in
the way it has been done in
Norway during the COVID
pandemic. In fact, we cannot see
that any attempt has been made
to justify this policy choice of
border closures for certain
groups over implementing other
border restrictions like
quarantining, testing and
vaccination requirements, beyond
the vague assumption that it
limits infections. Of course,
the ultimate verdict about
border closures in Norway, or
elsewhere, has to take an
overall, all-things-considered
form: everything we have said
provides only a pro tanto
reason to open borders. However,
pending further argumentation to
the contrary, we believe our
paper shows that the balance
of these reasons would favour
border restrictions over closed
borders.
Acknowledgements
Previous versions
of this paper have been
presented at an NTNU workshop on
The Ethics of the COVID-19
Pandemic, organised by the
Programme for Applied Ethics,
and at a workshop organised by
the Pluralism, Democracy and
Justice Research Group at UiT
The Arctic University of Norway.
We would like to thank the
participants for their comments.
We would also like to thank the
anonymous reviewers and editor
for their valuable suggestions
and insights. Finally, we would
like to thank the publication
fund of UiT The Arctic
University of Norway, who funded
the publication charges for this
article.
Notes
1 For a definition, see
Horst & Olsen (2021). 2 For a proper
characterization of COVID, see
Schwartz (2020). 3 For a recent
discussion, see Kraaijeveld (2020)
. 4 Owen (2020) is an
exception. 5 It
should be noted that there is also a
debate within the literature as to
whether the interests of citizens
might legitimate emigration
restrictions, in particular, in
relation to skilled health workers
(Brock & Blake, 2015). The idea
being discussed is the claim that
the need for providing health
services in countries, for example,
justify emigration restrictions.
Whereas Brock argues that they can,
subject to certain limitations,
Blake is more skeptical about using
such policies. We thank a reviewer
for drawing our attention to this
connection. 6 Partial border
closure is the policy of
banning entry by particular groups
of people based on their
nationality, for example. By
contrast, a complete border closure
refers to shutting the border to
everyone. Norway has endorsed the
former policy and has not been alone
in implementing such policies.
Indeed, most countries have
implemented complete or partial
border closures at various times
during the pandemic (Shiraef et al.,
2021).
7 See, for
example, Cogorno (2021). 8 Look for ‘registrert
smitte’ on VG’s online database (VG
2021). 9 Compare the UK
practice, for example Adams (2021). 10 Italy is a good
example. See Gedi Visual (2020)
under the heading “Distribuzione
dell'origine dei casi COVID-19
diagnosticati in Italia.” 11 The development,
introduction and widespread use of
vaccines (in particular, the new
mRNA vaccines) and the even more
recent development of medication
(COVID pills such as Paxlovid)
further strengthen this conclusion,
of course. However, it should be
noted that especially the former was
used also to open up borders
throughout the world. The emergence
of the latest COVID variant,
Omicron, appears to be changing this
picture as we write, however. Later
in the text, we argue that this
appearance is misleading.
12 In fact,
on 13.01.2021, the FrP has
demanded the physical closing of
borders (NTB 2021). And just two
weeks later (27.01.2021), their
wishes were fulfilled (Huse 2021). 13 See the rather damning
report of the Independent Panel for
Pandemic Preparedness Response in
Johnson Sirleaf and Clark (2021). 14 For these
classifications, see WHO “Tracking
SARS-CoV-2 variants.” 15 Thus, we are not
particularly supportive of the
drastic border measures that are
once again spreading in the world in
response to the recently discovered
Omicron variant (these words were
written in December 2021).
This new variant poses risks along
three dimensions: how infectious it
is (quickness of spread); how
dangerous it is (severity of
symptoms); how likely it is that it
bypasses bodily defenses
(vaccine-induced or otherwise). At
least at present there is a near
consensus regarding the first
dimension that the variant is very
likely to be more infectious than
even the Delta variant. The other
two dimensions are much harder to
assess and so the diagnosis of
epistemic poverty is more
appropriate here. However, what this
at most justifies are short-term,
targeted border closures (to
countries where there already is
community transmission) for the
period while we gain more knowledge
– this is presently roughly
estimated to take a couple of weeks
until we have community transmission
within Norway. Moreover, since we
have already had similar experiences
at least twice – the Alpha variant
and the Delta variant – by now we
have, or certainly should have, the
relevant systems in place to deal
with the situation without border
closures, such as border
restrictions in the form of testing,
quarantining and tracing). This is
also in line with WHO
recommendations. For more see
Harrison (2021). 16 For ongoing research
on the effects of COVID on
transnational families in Norway,
see Bell, Staver & Tolgensbakk
(forthcoming).
17 Although
the date has now passed, this
was particularly relevant when
writing the first draft of this
article, since Norway had
national elections in September
2021. 18 For details, see
Ekroll & Ask (2020). 19 The broader
theoretical background for the
argument that follows can be found
in McLeod & Tanyi
(forthcoming). 20 Consider for example
the Minister of Justice defending
her trip “home” as necessary
(Janssen 2020). 21 Specified
“essential” trips abroad for
Norwegian residents as of May 2021
include only such trips as those
for the birth of one’s child or
seeing seriously ill or dying
relatives (Ministry of Justice and
Public Security 2021).
22 There
is a parallel here with a
well-known argument from the
global justice literature:
Joseph Carens’ (2013, 238)
cantilever argument that argues
for a close analogy or even
logical connection between the
right to domestic freedom of
movement and international
freedom of movement. 23 We think, and in an
earlier draft of this paper have
elaborated upon how fleshing out
these considerations could be
turned into a consequentialist
argument against border closures.
The argument would run along
roughly two lines: how border
closures lead to damaging
exclusionary nationalism and how
they destroy social cohesion. We
also argue in that earlier draft
that interesting parallels exist
with the works of Blake (2002),
Egan (2020) and Cabrera (2020), as
well as with the empirical data in
Elias and others (2021). We thank
our reviewers for convincing us
that such a consequentialist
argument needs to be expanded
before it can be published in its
own right. 24 See for example
Helland (2021) or Sæbbe (2021). 25 Consider for example
the speech Sylvi Listhaug gave
when she became the new leader of
FrP (Heiervang & Krekling
2021) and contrast her claims with
the available data (Herbjørnsrud
2021).
Adams, R. (2021, 12 February). How do England's quarantine rules compare with those of other countries? Retrieved 10.08.2021 https://www.theguardian.com/politics/2021/feb/12/how-do-englands-quarantine-rules-compare-with-those-of-other-countries Altman, A., &
Wellman, C. H. (2011). A Liberal
Theory of International Justice.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bell, J., Staver, A.B., Tolgensbakk, I. (forthcoming). ‘Citizenship and Challenges to Transnational Family Life During the Pandemic’. Anthology on Citizenship from NOVA, Oslo Metropolitan University. Blake, M. (2002).
‘Discretionary Immigration’. Philosophical
Topics 30(2): 273-289. Blake, M. (2013).
‘Immigration, Jurisdiction,
and Exclusion’. Philosophy
& Public Affairs
41(2), 103-130. Brock, G.,
& Blake, M. (2015). Debating
Brain Drain: May
Governments Restrict
Emigration? New York,
NY: Oxford University Press. Cabrera, L.
(2020). ‘On Cosmopolitan
Humility and the Arrogance
of States’. Critical
Review of International
Social and Political
Philosophy 23(2):
163-187. Carens, J. H.
(2013). The Ethics of
Immigration. New York:
Oxford University Press. Cogorno, I. (2021, 26 March). Importsmitte har tatt over Oslo, men derfor stenges ikke grensene: – Et paradoks. Retrieved 09.08.2021 from https://www.ao.no/importsmitte-har-tatt-over-oslo-men-derfor-stenges-ikke-grensene-et-paradoks/s/5-128-72130 Devi, S. (2020). ‘Travel Restrictions Hampering COVID-19 Response’. Lancet 395(10233): 1331-2. Egan, M. S. (2020). ‘Statements on Race and Class: The Fairness of Skills-based Immigration Criteria’. Ethics & Global Politics 13(2): 108-122. Ekroll, H.
& Ask, A. (2020 24
March). Historisk
koronalov vedtatt av
Stortinget.
Retrieved 10.08.2021
from https://www.aftenposten.no/norge/politikk/i/kJjRRL/historisk-koronalov-vedtatt-av-stortinget
Elias,
E., Ben, J., Mansouri,
F., and Paradies, Y.
(2021). ‘Racism and
Nationalism During and
Beyond the COVID-19
Pandemic’. Ethnic
and Racial Studies
44(5): 783-793. Fange,
P. (2021, 28
February). Slik
har 5600 smittede
kommet til Norge
på et år.
Retrieved 09.08.2021
from https://www.nrk.no/osloogviken/slik-har-5600-smittede-kommet-til-norge-pa-et-ar-1.15391483
Fine, S. (2013). ‘The
Ethics of Immigration:
Self-Determination and the Right to
Exclude’. Philosophy Compass
8(3), 254-268.
Gedi Visual (2020). Coronavirus,
la situazione in Italia
[online database]. Retrieved
09.08.2021 from https://lab.gedidigital.it/gedi-visual/2020/coronavirus-i-contagi-in-italia/
Harrison, V. (2021, 29
November). Omicron variant: G7 to
hold emergency COVID meeting as
Japan closes its borders Retrieved
02.12.2021 fromhttps://www.theguardian.com/world/2021/nov/29/omicron-variant-g7-to-hold-emergency-COVID-meeting-as-japan-closes-its-borders
Haug, N., Geyrhofer,
L., Londei, A., (2020). ‘Ranking the
Effectiveness of Worldwide COVID-19
Government Interventions’. Nature
Human Behavior 4(12):
1303-1312.
Herbjørnsrud, D. (2021
5 March). Feil fra FHI og IMDi
om korona blant innvandrere
Retrieved 10.08.2021 from https://www.utrop.no/plenum/ytringer/247195/ Heiervang, C. &
Krekling, D. (2021 9 May). Listhaug
sammenligner klimapolitikken med
kommunisme Retrieved
10.08.2021 from https://www.nrk.no/norge/frp-leder-sylvi-listhaug-taler-til-landsmotet-1.15488792 Helland, A. (2021 15
January) - Kan ikke følge opp:
På disse flyene har det vært
koronasmitte. Nordlys. p. 10 Horst, C. and Olsen,
T.V. (2021), ‘Transnational
Citizens, Cosmopolitan Outlooks?
Migration as a Route to
Cosmopolitanism’. Nordic Journal
of Migration Research 11(1):
4-19.
Huse, G. (2021, 27
January). Norge stenger grensene
Retrieved 10.08.2021 from https://www.klartale.no/norge/norge-stenger-grensene-1.1826839 Janssen,
M. (2020, 11 April) - Å reise
hjem er ikke unødvendig
fritidsreise. Retrieved
10.08.2021 from https://www.dagbladet.no/nyheter/a-reise-hjem-er-ikke-unodvendig-fritidsreise/72351392 Johnson Sirleaf, E.,
Clark, H. (2021). ‘Report of the
Independent for Pandemic
Preparedness and Response: Making
COVID-19 the Last Pandemic’. The
Lancet 398(10295): 101-103. Kraaijeveld, S. R.
(2021). ‘COVID-19: Against a
Lockdown Approach’. Asian
Bioethics Review 13: 195-212. Mallapaty, S. (2021).
‘What the Data Say About Border
Closures and COVID Spread’. Nature
(London), 589(7841), 185. Marthinsen, R. (2020,
27 April). Vil forelenge
søringkarantena med ei uke.
Retrieved 10.08.2021 from https://ranano.no/vil-forelenge-soringkarantena-med-ei-uke/28.04-05:01
McLeod. S., Tanyi. A.
(forthcoming). ‘The Basic Liberties:
An Essay on Analytical
Specification’. Forthcoming in European
Journal of Political Theory. Miller, D. (2016).
Strangers in Our Midst: The
Political Philosophy of
Immigration. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Ministry of Foreign
Affairs (2021, 18 June). Reopening:
Gradual introduction of a safe
travel framework [Press
release]. Retrieved from https://www.regjeringen.no/en/aktuelt/reopening/id2862254/ Ministry of Justice
and Public Security (2021, 12
March). More people must go
into hotel quarantine and entry
restrictions to be extended
[Press release]. Retrieved from https://www.regjeringen.no/en/aktuelt/more-people-must-go-into-hotel-quarantine-and-entry-restrictions-to-be-extended/id2838529/
Nickel, James (1994).
‘Rethinking Rawls’s Theory of
Liberty and Rights’. Chicago-Kent
Law Review, 69(3), 763–785. NTB Nyheter (2021, 13
January) Frp krever fysisk
stengte grenser. Retrieved
10.08.2021from https://www.dagsavisen.no/nyheter/innenriks/frp-krever-fysisk-stengte-grenser-1.1822008 Office of the Prime
Minister (a) (2021, 27 January). Norway
introduces its strictest entry
rules since March 2020
[Press release]. Retrieved from https://www.regjeringen.no/en/aktuelt/norway-introduces-its-strictest-entry-rules-since-march-2020/id2830390/
Office of the Prime
Minister. (b) (2021, 18 June). The
Norwegian Government is
continuing to reopen society
[Press release]. Retrieved from https://www.regjeringen.no/en/aktuelt/the-norwegian-government-is-continuing-to-reopen-society/id2862266/ Owen, D. (2020), ‘Open Borders and the COVID-19 Pandemic’. Democratic Theory 7(2): 152-159 Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Rawls,
J. (2005). Political
Liberalism.
New York, NY:
Columbia
University
Press.
Originally
published in
1993. Rawls,
John (2001). Justice
as Fairness: A
Restatement,
ed. by Erin
Kelly. Harvard
University
Press. Saxena,
A., Bouvier,
P.A.,
Shamsi-Gooshki,
E., Köhler,
J., and
Schwartz, L.J.
(2021), ‘WHO
Guidance on
Ethics in
Outbreaks and
the COVID-19
Pandemic: A
Critical
Appraisal’. Journal
of Medical
Ethics 47:
367-373. Scheall,
S., Crutchfield, P.
(2021), ‘A Case Study in
the Problem of
Policymaker Ignorance:
Political Responses to
COVID-19’. Cosmos +
Taxis 9(5-6):
18-28. Schwartz,
M. C. (2020). ed. The
Ethics of Pandemics.
Broadview Press. Shiraef, M. A., Hirst, C., Weiss, M. A., Naseer, S., Lazar, N., Beling, E., Walker, B. (2021). ‘COVID Border Accountability Project, a hand-coded global database of border closures introduced during 2020’. Scientific Data 8(1): 253-253.
Song, S.
(2018). Political Theories
of Migration. Annual
review of political
science 21(1):
385-402.
Sæbbe, L. (2021
21 January) Polske Piotr
ber Tromsøs befolkning om
å tenke seg om: – Vi
kjenner på hets og ubehag.
Nordlys. p. 18-19 Voigt, A.,
Martyushenko, N., Karlsen,
E., Hall, M., Nyhamar, K.,
Omholt, S.W., and Almaas, E.
(forthcoming). ‘Containing
pandemics through targeted
testing of households’.
Forthcoming in BMC
Infectious Diseases. Wellman, C. H. (2020). ‘Immigration’. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/immigration/ World Health Organization. (2021, 29 February). Updated WHO recommendations for international traffic in relation to COVID-19 outbreak [Press release]. Retrieved from https://www.who.int/news-room/articles-detail/updated-who-recommendations-for-international-traffic-in-relation-to-COVID-19-outbreak World Health Organization (2021). Tracking SARS-CoV-2 Variants. Retrieved from https://www.who.int/en/activities/tracking-SARS-CoV-2-variants/
|