Etikk i praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2021),
15
(1), 51-73 |
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v15i1.3980 |
Abortion and multifetal pregnancy
reduction: An ethical comparison
Silje Langseth Dahl,a Rebekka
Hylland Vaksdal,b Mathias Barra,c Espen Gamlund,d
Carl Tollef Solberge a Universitetet i
Bergen, silje.langseth.dahl@gmail.com b Universitetet i
Bergen, rvaksdal@gmail.com c HØKH—Avdeling
for helsetjenesteforskning, Akershus
universitetssykehus, mathias.barra@ahus.no d Institutt for
filosofi og førstesemesterstudier (FOF), Universitetet
i Bergen. espen.gamlund@uib.no e Institutt for
global helse og samfunnsmedisin (IGS), Universitetet i
Bergen, carl.solberg@uib.no
In recent years, multifetal pregnancy reduction (MFPR) has increasingly been a subject of debate in Norway. The intensity of this debate reached a tentative maximum when the Legislation Department delivered their interpretative statement, Section 2 - Interpretation of the Abortion Act, in 2016 in response to a request from the Ministry of Health (2014) that the Legislation Department consider whether the Abortion Act allows for MFPR of healthy fetuses in multiple pregnancies. The Legislation Department concluded that the current abortion legislation [as of 2016] allows for MFPR subject to the constraints that the law otherwise stipulates. The debate has not subsided, and during autumn 2018 it was further intensified in connection with the Norwegian Christian Democratic "crossroads" policy and signals from the Conservatives to consider removing section 2.3c and to forbid MFPR. Many of the arguments in the MFPR debate are seemingly similar to arguments put forward in the general abortion debate, and an analysis to ascertain what distinguishes MFPR from other abortions has yet to be conducted. The aim of this article is, therefore, to examine whether there is a moral distinction between abortion and MFPR of healthy fetuses. We will cover the typical arguments emerging in the debate in Norway and exemplify them with scholarly articles from the literature. We have dubbed the most important arguments against MFPR that we have identified the harm argument, the slippery-slope argument, the intention argument, the grief argument, the long-term psychological effects for the woman argument, and the sorting argument. We conclude that these arguments do not measure up in terms of demonstrating a morally relevant difference between MFPR of healthy fetuses and other abortions. Our conclusion is, therefore — despite what several discussants seem to think — that there is no morally relevant difference between the two. Therefore, on the same conditions as we allow for abortions, we should also allow MFPR. Keywords: abortion, ethics, medical ethics, MFPR,
selective MFPR Introduction The right to self-determined
abortion has been recognised in Norway
since 1976 (Abortloven 1976), but it is
still a subject of debate (Austveg 2017).
Notwithstanding, the right to
self-determined abortion before the end of
the 12th week of pregnancy is
more or less accepted (Pew Research Center
2018), although an increasing number of
voices are calling for a tightening of the
legislation (Menneskeverd, Kristelig
folkeparti 2018 (the Christian Democratic
Party), Solberg 2018). In recent years,
MFPR has increasingly been a subject of
debate in Norway. The intensity of this
discussion reached a tentative climax when
the Legislation Department delivered its
statement, Section 2 - Interpretation of
the Abortion Act, in 2016 as a
response to the Ministry of Health’s
[2014] request addressed to the
Legislation Department for an
interpretation of whether “the
Act of 13 June 1975 on Termination of
pregnancy (hereinafter Abortion Act)
allows for MFPR of healthy fetuses in
cases of multiple pregnancies.”
(Lovavdelingen 2016). The legislation
Department refers to historical documents
(NOU1991:6, Ot.prp.35) in their reply and
concludes: The Abortion Act allows
multifetal pregnancy reduction within the
limits the law otherwise stipulates. This
means that it is legal to grant multifetal
pregnancy reductions on healthy fetuses on
the basis of the woman’s health, cf. the
Abortion Act (medical indication) or on
the basis of her situation, ref. Abortion
Act §2, third section, letter b (social
indication) or letter a, or a combination
of these grounds. There is also no basis
for excluding cases where multifetal
pregnancy reduction occurs before the end
of the 12th week of gestation
on the basis of self-determination, cf.
Abortion Act §2, second section. Our
interpretation is based on the assumption
that multifetal pregnancy reduction is
carried out so that the selection is
random, and that there is no selection
between fetuses on a basis other than
those which the Abortion Act allows for,
ref.
2, section 3, letter c. The
debate has not subsided, and MFPR together
with the Abortion Act’s section 2.3c –
which allows abortion when the fetus is
unhealthy – are central to the discussion
(Sørvig 2017, Menneskeverd, Barra &
Augestad 2016, Clemet 2018, Saugstad
2018). We have seen comprehensive
involvement and discussions marked by
legal, medical, and ethical argumentation.
However, many of the ethical arguments
pertaining to MFPR are similar to the
arguments applicable to the right to
abortion itself. What is the debate really
about? It is unclear whether MFPR is a
topic that is inextricably linked to the
discussion on abortion, or whether MFPR is
a special and separate debate. We therefore pose the following question in this article: Is there any morally significant distinction between abortion and MFPR on healthy fetuses? We explain what MFPR is, presenting the background for the Norwegian debate, and consider pertinent legislation in some of the other Nordic countries. We then discuss the main ethical arguments for and against MFPR. Finally, we conclude that there is no relevant moral difference between abortion and MFPR on healthy fetuses. Multifetal pregnancy reduction MFPR reduces the number of fetuses
in multiple pregnancies, e.g., from three
to two, or from two to one fetus; experts
often refer to “3–to–1” or “4–to–2”
reductions when this level of precision is
required. The procedure, which is
currently regarded as permitted1
under Norwegian law (Lovavdelingen 2016),
is performed by injecting potassium
chloride into the fetal heart via an
ultrasound-guided puncture through the
mother’s abdomen, uterus, and fetal
membranes. Nonselective MFPR chooses the
fetus that is most accessible. The
procedure is not possible on monochorionic
pregnancies (identical
twins sharing a placenta; Evans, MI,
Andriole, Evans, SM & Britt 2015: 97).
MFPR is best carried out between gestation
weeks nine and fourteen (Mark Evans,
personal correspondence, Zemet et al.
2018:94). In Norway, the term nonselective
MFPR is used for the reduction of the
number of fetuses in a pregnancy with
apparently healthy fetuses, while the term
selective MFPR (or selective feticide) is
used for MFPR on a fetus based on findings
from prenatal diagnostics, and for such
cases, section 2.3c is relevant. We will
mainly discuss the ethical aspects of
nonselective MFPR but will also bring in
selective MFPR when relevant. MFPR
in Norway
MFPR is first mentioned in official
documents in [the governmental white paper]
NOU1991:6 Biotechnology, authored by the
Skjæraasen Committee. It states that: [B]y
selective [MFPR] we understand the practice of
reducing the number of fetuses in the uterus by
ensuring that one or more of the fetuses die,
while the others develop. This can theoretically
be applicable to both natural multiple
pregnancies and those resulting from IVF
treatment. The Commission believes it should not
be permitted to perform selective [MFPR] in
these cases. This question is not currently
regulated in the Act on Abortion (NOU1991:6,
p.5). The Legislation Department of the
then Norwegian Ministry of Health and Social
Affairs wrote about MFPR in a letter dated 19th
of December 2000 (Lovavdelingen 2000). They
concluded that an abortion panel may grant MFPR
if one or more fetuses have a condition that
would otherwise give grounds for abortion during
singleton pregnancy, cf. Abortion Act section
2.3c, related to abortions after 12 weeks’
gestation. This statement thus concerns
selective MFPR. Reduction of healthy fetuses,
i.e., nonselective MFPR, was not discussed in
this report. However, reference is made to
NOU1991:6, and the Legislation Department
clearly distances itself from the Skjæraasen
Committee’s reading of the Abortion Act.
[a]
pregnancy [leads] to serious difficulties for a
woman, she should be offered information and
guidance on the assistance which the community
can offer her. The woman is entitled to counsel
for being able to make her final choice. Finding
that the woman, after she has been offered
guidance [...] still cannot carry the pregnancy
to term, she makes the final decision about
abortion unless the procedure cannot take place
before the end of the twelfth week of pregnancy
and there are solid medical reasons for not
doing so. After the end of the twelfth week of
pregnancy, abortion can be granted, subject to
an abortion panel, and only on the basis of
especially weighty reasons. (The Abortion Act
1976). In April 2014 the
Norwegian Ministry of Health and Social Affairs
asked the Legislation Department to assess
whether the Abortion Act allows for MFPR of
healthy fetuses, also based on subsection a
and/or b (medical and/or social indication) of
section 2.3 of the Abortion Act. In February 2016 the Legislation
Department concluded that MFPR should be
allowed within the constraints laid out in the
Abortion Act. This interpretation was
explicitly conditional on the assumption that
MFPR is performed by random selection of the
fetus to be terminated, and that there should
be no selection between fetuses on any basis
other than the criteria stipulated in the
Abortion Act. The decision consequently meant
that the woman herself may decide whether to
have an MFPR procedure up until the end of the
twelfth week of pregnancy, and that granting
the procedure at any later stage of gestation
must follow the general criteria that apply to
other second-trimester abortions. This
prevents selection based on factors such as
gender (Lovavdelingen 2016) and means that
both selective and nonselective MFPR are to be
considered as lawfully regulated by the
currently applicable Abortion Act.
MFPR in the Nordic countries The practice and the legal
aspects of MFPR in the Nordic countries
differ somewhat. Norway is the only
Nordic country in which the government
has concluded that MFPR is allowed on
par with abortion. Denmark is the
only Nordic country that has adopted
separate legislation for MFPR. The Danish
act of 2005 allows MFPR if the procedure
can be completed by the end of the twelfth
week of pregnancy and if, in addition, one
of the following three conditions is met:
a) the pregnancy poses a serious danger to
the mother’s life or health, b) MFPR
reduces the risk that the pregnancy will
result in a miscarriage of all fetuses, or
c) one or more fetuses will be unviable or
will suffer from a serious illness as a
result of premature birth. After the
twelfth week of pregnancy, the procedure
can take place only if the requirements of
MFPR are met, and a competent tribunal
approves the petition (Sundhedsloven 2005,
sections 92-96). According to the Danish
legislation, MFPR is permitted only if the
woman is carrying three or more fetuses.
It is not permitted to perform MFPR on
twin pregnancies in Denmark unless there
are specific circumstances
(Retsinformation 2006).
Discussion Likely, people who oppose
abortion will also oppose MFPR.
Furthermore, it is reasonable to imagine
that those who argue that MFPR is morally
permissible will likewise argue that
abortion is morally acceptable. Still, not
everyone who endorses abortion will also
endorse MFPR. We examine the extent to
which it seems reasonable that endorsement
of abortion on healthy fetuses should
logically entail endorsement of the right
to MFPR on healthy fetuses. The
fetus’ moral status
Although we have not seen
arguments directly related to the fetus’
moral status in the MFPR debate, we want to
devote some space to this subject because
the view on moral status can influence the
discussion of the various arguments.
Questions regarding the fetus’ moral status
and fetal rights have been raised throughout
the lengthy debate on abortion, and there is
no general consensus on this contested
issue. A diversity of values and views, as
well as religious and moral perceptions, is
presented (Chervenak, McCullough &
Wapner 1992: 84). Some philosophers have
argued that abortion is morally unacceptable
because it robs the fetus of its future, in
the same way as one robs a child of his/her
future by killing the child (e.g. Marquis
1989: 183). Other philosophers have
concluded that although a fetus certainly
has the potential to become a human being,
it nevertheless has no right to life in the
fetal stage – no right, that is, that trumps
the woman’s right to protect her health,
freedom, and life (e.g. Warren 1973: 43). In
addition, there are those who believe that
the fetus does not have an independent moral
status, but rather a dependent moral status,
which is directly linked to the woman’s
autonomy (e.g. Chervenak et al. 1992: 84).
Arguments
against MFPR
In the following, we will look
at the arguments that advocate against MFPR
and suggest that there is a morally relevant
difference between abortion and MFPR. We
will discuss the harm argument, the
slippery-slope argument, the
intention argument3, the grief
argument, long-term psychological
effects for the woman, and the
sorting argument.
The harm argument
In the debate on MFPR there is
one argument in particular that is
recurrent, and that we have chosen to call
the harm argument (Clemet 2016, Henden
2016b, Nilsen 2016, Rognsvåg and Weiby 2016,
Saugstad 2016b). The harm argument asserts
that MFPR is morally unacceptable because it
involves a risk of harm to the remaining
fetuses, and in the Norwegian debate it is
mainly the risk of miscarriage that has been
in focus. It is widely accepted that those
who intend to bring a new person into the
world have a great responsibility for the
health of that future person, even among
those who do not ascribe a moral status to
the fetus. In practice, this is expressed as
the mother-to-be’s duty not to smoke, drink
alcohol, or use other teratogenic drugs
during pregnancy (Woollard 2016: 126).
The slippery-slope argumentOla Didrik Saugstad, professor emeritus of paediatrics at the University of Oslo, has argued that MFPR leads to ‘extreme sorting’. The reason for this is that one can obtain information about diseases, characteristics, and congenital conditions of the fetus before the end of the twelfth week of pregnancy. He points to the possibility that someone in the future will be able to choose to abort a fetus on the basis of characteristics such as gender, sexual orientation, or skills (Saugstad 2016a, Saugstad 2016b). However, it is the case in Norway that prenatal diagnosis – regardless of whether it is a singleton or a multiple pregnancy – is offered to women with risk-pregnancies, such as women above the age of 38 years, or at increased risk of chromosomal abnormalities (Røe, Salvesen & Eggebø 2012). One can imagine that Saugstad’s statement is rooted in a fear of a slippery-slope effect associated with the use of prenatal diagnosis. A slippery slope argument is premised on a belief that the implementation of a relatively moderate proposals may start a chain of events that ultimately leads to an ethically undesirable outcome (Haigh, Wood & Stewart 2016:819).
The intention argument
Is it morally permissible
that a woman who genuinely wants children
has the right to determine the number of
children she should have? Some will argue
that if the woman desires children, she
must accept to have more than she
initially planned to have. (Clemet 2016,
Det Etiske Råd 2016, Skogedal & Jemli
2017, NTB 2019). Let us call this the intention
argument. Naturally, some will
regard this as contradictory. Imagine a
woman A,
who is pregnant with multiple fetuses and
who wants to reduce the number of fetuses
for no other reason than that she wants
fewer children – that is, completely
independent of factors such as the risk of
mortality and morbidity entailed in
carrying a multiple pregnancy to term. She
may, for example, have financial concerns.
We can compare this woman with woman B,
a pregnant woman who already has children
and who chooses to have an abortion for
the same reasons. We thus encounter two
pregnant women, both of whom want
children, but only a certain number of
children, and for the same reasons. Let us
further assume that all other factors are
equal between woman A
and woman B. The Abortion Act provides
woman B with an option to freely
choose this until the end of the twelfth
week of pregnancy without having health
care professionals or the government
second-guessing whether the woman’s
reasons are valid. Based on this, it is
difficult to imagine that woman B,
who wants an abortion, has a stronger
right to decide the number of children she
wants to carry to term than woman A,
who wants an MFPR.
The grief argument
Some of the arguments against
MFPR have focused on the remaining child’s
grief from losing a potential sibling
(Hegertun 2016, Kirkeberg and Næsheim 2018,
Lund 2018). We choose to call this the grief
argument. One can imagine that
significant distress will result in a child
growing up with the knowledge that he or she
might have had a twin. An adult twin has
commented that “growing up without my twin
sister is completely unimaginable for me”,
and further, that “if one does away with the
one, the other loses a part of herself”
(Henden 2016a). It is understandable that a
child who has grown up with a twin cannot
imagine anything else. But is this any
different for a child who has grown up with
a non-twin sibling? Also, in this latter
case, it appears difficult to imagine a
childhood without the sibling.
Long-term psychological
effects for the woman
It is natural to discuss
whether MFPR might entail psychological
consequences for the mother, or more generally,
for both parents. There have been numerous
studies investigating this issue specifically.
In one study, it was reported that a third of
the mothers experience symptoms of depression
and guilt one year after MFPR. These symptoms,
however, were largely absent after two years of
follow-up. Compared with mothers of triplets who
did not undergo MFPR, the MFPR group reportedly
had lower levels of anxiety and depression
shortly after the procedure, as well as fewer
problems linked to psychological attachment to
the children born (Garel et al. 1997: 617).
Other studies have shown similar results, with
some of the women and parents reporting grief,
remorse, and feelings of guilt shortly after
they had undergone MPFR, but any long-term
psychological effects appear to be mild
(McKinney, Downey & Timor-Tritsch 1995: 51,
Sentilhes et al. 2008: 295, Schreiner-Engel,
Walther, Midnex, Lynch & Berkowitz 1995:
541). It was also found that women who had had a
MFPR performed were not subject to
elevated risk of developing depression or other
mental disorders compared to pregnant women or
new mothers who had not had MFPR (McKinney et
al. 1995: 51). All of 93% of the women who
participated in one of the studies reported that
they would make the same decision on MFPR again
in the same situation (Schreiner-Engel et al.
1995: 541).
The sorting argument
Some argue that MFPR may not
only lead to sorting based on
characteristics such as sex and
developmental anomalies, but it may also
result in a society in which twins will feel
discriminated against and generally unwanted
(Rognsvåg & Weiby 2016). We call this
the sorting
argument. For example, as Saugstad
asks: ‘[...] what will MFPR on twins do with
our view of human relations in general and
of twins in particular?’ Moreover, he argues
that we need to consider any harm MFPR
confers on twins, both those who already
exist, and for those who are survivors after
such an intervention (Saugstad 2016b). The
concern that Saugstad raises can be
recognised as a variant of the
slippery-slope argument: the acceptance of
MFPR will cause a drift towards a generally
negative sentiment against multiple births.
But is it reasonable to attribute weight to
the possibility that twins as a group may
feel stigmatised because we have allowed
MFPR for twin pregnancies? And is it
plausible that we will have a society in
which twins [in general] are not wanted?
Arguments in favour of MFPR We will now consider arguments
in favour of MFPR. We will consider parental
autonomy and discuss why selective,
section 2.3c indicated, MFPR is not
sufficient (to secure basic reproductive
rights). Parental Autonomy
Respect for autonomy, or
self-determination, is one of the key
principles of medical ethics (Gillon 2003:
307). Through respect for autonomy, we
recognise the patients’ right to their own
opinions, their own bodies, and their own
health, and their right to make choices
based on personal values and beliefs. For the decision
to have an abortion or an MFPR, it is
particularly important that women receive
adequate information about treatment
options. As a preventive measure, the
information must deal with how society can
assist her if she chooses to carry the
pregnancy to term. This provides the basis
for informed consent, which is central to
the principle of respect for autonomy (ACOG
Committee 2013: 405). When abortion
legislation ensures respect for women’s
autonomy in their decision whether to have
an abortion, why should not the same respect
be extended to a woman who desires an MFPR
intervention? The woman’s body, health, life
situation, and family are affected to an
equal extent. If she feels that it would be
too great a burden to bring as many children
into the world as the number of fetuses she
is pregnant with, she should not be forced
to terminate the pregnancy by abortion when
we are now able to offer her the choice to
retain one or more of the fetuses.
Why selective MFPR is not
sufficient
Some will argue that there is a
significant moral difference between
selective MFPR and MFPR on healthy fetuses.
Understandably, the termination of a fetus
with severe somatic illness or disorder may
be perceived as more morally acceptable than
the termination of a healthy fetus.
Philosopher Leah McClimmans defends
selective MFPR, partly on the basis of the lifeboat
principle. She compares a multiple
pregnancy with a sinking lifeboat carrying
more passengers than its authorised
capacity, arguing that it may be acceptable
to sacrifice some individuals so that all do
not perish. She next questions if the force
of this argument is weakened when applied to
MFPR on healthy fetuses. She argues that it
is reasonable to assume that parents who
want nonselective MFPR believe that not
reducing the number of fetuses would also
cause suffering or injury. McClimmans
emphasises that it is problematic to use
only medical facts and diagnoses to guide
ethical decisions. Empirical facts, she
argues, are not ethically normative, since
they are based exclusively on biological
aspects of health (McClimmans 2010: 295).
Should MFPR be legal? We have demonstrated that none
of the objections raised appear
significantly more valid for MFPR than for
ordinary abortions. In addition, we have
highlighted the right to self-determination
as an equally important argument in favour
of MFPR as it is for self-determined
abortion. In Norway, the right to
self-determined abortions has been
guaranteed by legislation for more than 40
years. It was difficult, of course, to
predict that our society eventually would
have to take a stance on MFPR when the
Abortion Act was drafted, and it is easy to
understand that permitting new medical
procedures that deal with life and death
lead to a new heated debate. Based on our
discussion, however, we find no evidence for
the proposition that a country with
legalised abortion should not also allow
MFPR on healthy fetuses14.
Conclusion
The aim of this article was
to discuss whether there is any
significant moral distinction between
abortion and MFPR. First, we considered
the arguments against MFPR. We discussed
the harm argument, the slippery-slope
argument, the intention argument, the
grief argument, long-term psychological
effects for the woman, and the sorting
argument. Then we considered the
arguments in favour of MFPR, with an
emphasis on parental autonomy and why
selective MFPR is not sufficient. Our
conclusion is that if abortion is
morally permissible, it appears
reasonable that MFPR should also be
morally permissible. This applies unless
there exists compelling research
presenting results that establish risks
or harm to the remaining fetuses or to
the pregnant woman that we have
overlooked. Consequently,
it seems reasonable that the issue of
the moral acceptability of MFPRs turns
on whether abortions, in general, are
morally acceptable. Acknowledgements Thanks to Mark
Evans and Birgitte Kahrs for help with
medical evidence, and to two anonymous
referees for valuable suggestions which
improved the article. We would also like
to thank Tim Challman and Gavin for help
with this English translation.
Notes
1 At the
time of proofreading of this article, there
is an amendment to the Abortion Act out for
public consultation which seeks to ban
self-determined MFPR (Ministry of Health and
Care Services 2019). The very recent debate
and events are also illuminated in footnotes
7 and 11. At the time of this translation to
English, the Norwegian Abortion Act has been
amended. It now, in 2020, asserts that MFPR
is a form of abortion and is regulated by
the Abortion Act. It also states that MFPR
is not available to women by
self-determination, and MFPR cannot be
performed without the permission from an
abortion panel, regardless of the timing of
the procedure. The law furthermore places
additional restrictions on 2-to-1
reductions, and effectively prohibit these. 2 The figures for
completed MFPR are valid up to 23 November
2018. 3 The
intention argument includes the imperative
"If you can manage one, then you should be
able to manage two" (NTB 2019). 4 And, more
recently, again in Dagsavisen April 2019,
Evans calls the Norwegian assessment of MFPR
‘bullshit’.
https://www.dagsavisen.no/innenriks/sabler-ned-det-norske-fagmiljoet-1.1468910 5 The
Norwegian Abortion Act’s section 2.3c
regulates second-trimester abortions on
indication of fetal anomaly. 6 Some have
nevertheless suggested that fetal reduction
itself is a form of sorting, since one fetus
‘is selected’ (Saugstad 2016a). It is a
curiosity that the term ‘sort’
etymologically derives from the Latin
“sortiri”, meaning ‘to choose by lot’. The
connotations of the Norwegian word ‘sort’,
however, is in a certain sense the opposite:
‘to organise into categories, grouping
according to specific criteria’. 7 ‘If you can
manage one, you can manage two’ (NTB 2019).
In the proposed amendment to the Abortion
Act, addressing MFPR, the intention argument
is clearly recognisable in phrases about how
triplet pregnancies may be reduced to twins,
but not to singletons. (MOH 2019). 8 There are probably
many children who will never know that their
parents have carried out MFPR or an
abortion. It is hard to imagine that this
could have an impact on the lives of these
children, and therefore such cases are not
appreciably relevant to the grief argument. 9 Although,
in the event of a large number of fetuses,
e.g., four or more, it can be argued that
reducing the number to two is a moral
imperative on a par with not smoking or
refraining from using drugs, [given the
clear and unequivocal benefits of such
reductions.] 10 We recognise that
Norwegians born after 1976 are not a minority in
society, but that twins are. It is natural
to assume that twins may experience that
part of their identity is linked with
being twins. 11 We have
not argued that there is a necessary
relationship between (1) opposing MFPR in
healthy fetuses and (2) opposing the right
to [selective] abortion on anomalous fetuses
(cf. section 2.3c). However, it is an
empirical fact that the two major
organisations that have spoken out most
strongly against MFPR – The Christian
Democratic Party and the Human Dignity
[Menneskeverd] organisation – also advocate
strongly against section 2.3c. 12 We have
not argued here that (1) rejecting MFPR of
healthy fetuses and (2) rejecting abortion
of abnormal fetuses is causally connected
(cf section 2.3c). It remains an empirical
fact that the two major [Norwegian]
organisations that have advocated the
banning of MFPR – KrF and Menneskeverd –
also advocate against section 2.3c. 13 A
phenomenon that also applies to chromosomal
abnormalities. 14 The fact
that something is permitted
does not necessarily mean that it comes with
a right
attached, and under a priority setting
perspective it can, of course, be debatable
whether MFPR on healthy twins should be
offered (free of charge) on request. There
is no doubt that an MFPR is something quite
different from a regular abortion and
requires a lot more resources and expertise
– even if we conclude that the involved
ethics are comparable. Besides, we have not
discussed how reservation issues come into
play, and one can imagine that healthcare
professionals might have reservations
specifically against participating in MFPRs
(just as it is possible to have reservations
against participating in abortions today in
Norway). Aastebøl, I. (2016). Ja, så
utrydd meg, da! Det er viktigere at
abortloven finnes om 30 år, enn at det
finnes tvillinger. Aftenposten.
https://www.aftenposten.no/meninger/debatt/i/m5vp/Ja_-sa-utrydd- Abortlag. (1974). (1974:595).
http://www.riksdagen.se/sv/dokument-lagar/dokument/svenskforfattningssamling/abortlag-1974595_sfs- Abortloven. (1976). Lov om
svangerskapsavbrudd (LOV-1975-06-13-50).
https://lovdata.no/dokument/NL/lov/1975-06-13-50
(Accessed 12 February 2018). ACOG Committee. (2013). ACOG
Committee opinion no. 553: multifetal
pregnancy reduction. Obstetrics &
Gynecology 121(2 Pt 1): 405-410. Austveg, B. (2017). ABORT
en etisk argumentasjon (1. utg.).
Oslo: Humanist forlag Barra, M. & Augestad, L. A.
(2016). Faglige råd i fosterreduksjonssaken.
Dagens medisin.
https://www.dagensmedisin.no/artikler/2016/04 Biggs, M. A., Upadhyay U. D.,
McCulloch, C. E. & Foster D. G. (2017).
Women’s Mental Health and Well-Being 5 Years
after Receiving or Being Denied an Abortion:
A Prospective, Longitudinal Cohort Study. JAMA
Psychiatry 74(2): 169-178.
CrossRef Cheong-See, F., Schuit, E., Arroyo-Manzano, D., Khalil, A., Barrett, J., Joseph, K. S., Thangaratinam, S. (2016). Prospective Risk of Stillbirth and Neonatal Complications in Twin Pregnancies: Systematic Review and Meta-Analysis. British Medical Journal 354:i4353. CrossRef Chervenak, F. A., McCullough,
L. B. & Wapner, R. J. (1992). Selective
termination to a singleton pregnancy is
ethically justified. Ultrasound in Obstetrics
& Gynecology 2(2): 84-87. CrossRef Clemet, K. (2016). Et foster
for mye? Civita. https://www.civita.no Clemet, K. (2018). Paragraf 2c:
Prinsipielt og moralsk viktig. Civita.
http://clemet.blogg.no/1541008119_paragraf_2c_prinsipielt_og_
moralsk_viktig.html (Accessed 12 November
2018). Coleman, P. K. (2011). Abortion
and mental health: quantitative synthesis
and analysis of research published
1995-2009. The British Journal of
Psychiatry 199(3): 180-186.
CrossRef
Det Etiske Råd. (2016). Det
Etiske Råds udtalelse om
fosterantalsreduktion.
http://www.etiskraad.dk/etiske-temaer/abort-og-fosterdiagnostik Evans, M. I., Kaufman, M. I.,
Urban, A. J., Britt, D. W. & Fletcher,
J. C. (2004). Fetal reduction from twins to
a singleton: a reasonable consideration? Obstetrics
& Gynecology 104(1): 102-9.
CrossRef Evans, M. I. & Britt, D. W.
(2010). Multifetal Pregnancy Reduction:
Evolution of the Ethical Arguments. Seminars
in Reproductive Medicine
28(4):295-302.
CrossRef. Evans, M. I., Andriole, S.
& Britt, D. W. (2014). Fetal reduction:
25 years’ experience. Fetal diagnosis
and therapy 35(2): 69-82. https://doi.org/
10.1159/000357974
Evans, M. I., Andriole, S.,
Evans, S. M. & Britt, D. W. (2015).
Medical Reasons for Pregnancy Interruption:
Fetal Reduction. I: J. P. Galst, M. S. Verp
(Red), Prenatal and Preimplantation
Diagnosis (s. 97-117). New York:
Springer.
CrossRef Evans, M. I. (2016). Uvitenhet
– eller feilaktig skråsikkerhet. Dagens
medisin.
https://www.dagensmedisin.no/artikler/2016/05/13/uvitenhet--eller- Förordning om avbrytande av
havandeskap. (1970).
http://finlex.fi/sv/laki/ Ganatra, B. (2008). Maintaining
Access to Safe Abortion and Reducing Sex
Ratio Imbalances in Asia. Reproductive
Health Matters 16(sup31):90-98. Garel, M., Stark, C., Blondel,
B., Lefebvre, G., Vauthier-Brouzes, D. &
Zorn, J. R. (1997). Psychological reactions
after multifetal pregnancy reduction: a
2-year follow-up study. Human
reproduction 12(3): 617-622.
CrossRef Gillon, R. (2003). Ethics needs
principles - four can encompass the rest -
and respect for autonomy should be “first
among equals”. Journal of Medical Ethics
29(5): 307-312.
CrossRef Gupta, S., Fox, N., Feinberg, J., Klauser, C.K., Rebarber, A. (2015). Outcomes in twin pregnancies reduced to singleton pregnancies compared with ongoing twin pregnancies. American Journal of Obstetrics & Gynecology 213(4):580.e1-580.e5. CrossRef Haigh, M., Wood, J. S. &
Stewart, A. J. (2016). Slippery slope
arguments imply opposition to change. Memory
& Cognition 44(5): 819-836.
CrossRef Hasson, J., Shapira, A., Many,
A., Jaffa, A. & Har-Toov, J. (2011).
Reduction of twin pregnancy to singleton:
does it improve pregnancy outcome? The Journal
of Maternal-Fetal & Neonatal Medicine
24(11):1362-1366.
CrossRef Helsedirektoratet. (2014).
Helsedirektoratets vurderinger i forbindelse
med fosterreduksjon for abortsøkende kvinner
med flerlingesvangerskap.
https://helsedirektoratet.no/Documents/Lovfortolkninger/Abortloven Henden, A. (2016a). Jeg er for
abort, men jeg er også tvilling. Og norsk
lov gir meg bakoversveis. Aftenposten.
https://www.aftenposten.no/meninger/ Henden, A. (2016b). Fire
problemer med tvillingabort – uten føleri. Aftenposten.
Hentet november 25, 2018, fra:
https://www.aftenposten.no/meninger/ Hegertun, A. (2016). Elvis
savnet tvillingbroren sin hele livet. Aftenposten. https://www.aftenposten.no/meninger/debatt/i/4zM6/Elvis-savnet- Kirkeberg, K.J. & Næsheim,
A.A. (2018). Aftenposten.
https://www.aftenposten.
no/meninger/sid/i/5VzXmz/Du-hadde-en- Kristelig folkeparti. (2018).
Sortering og tvillingabort – Hva mener
egentlig Krf?
https://www.krf.no/nyheter/nyheter-fra-krf/sortering-og-tvillingabort/
Lund, S. S. (2018). Jeg kan
ikke forestille meg et liv uten
tvillingbroren min. Aftenposten.
https://www.aftenposten.no/meninger/sid/i/l107nA/Jeg- Lovavdelingen. (2000). § 2 –
Tolkning av lov av 13. juni 1975 nr. 50 om
svangerskapsavbrudd.
https://www.regjeringen.no/no/dokumenter Lovavdelingen. (2016). § 2 -
Tolkning av abortloven.
https://www.regjeringen. Major, B., Cozzarelli, C. &
Cooper, M. (2000) Psychological Responses of
Women After First-Trimester Abortion. Archives
of General Psychiatry 57(8): 777-784.
CrossRef
Marquis, D. (1989). Why abortion is immoral. The Journal of Philosophy 86(4): 183-202. CrossRef McClimmans, L. (2010). Elective
twin reductions: evidence and ethics. Bioethics
24(6): 295-303.
CrossRef McKinney, M., Downey, J. &
Timor-Tritsch, I. (1995). The psychological
effects of multifetal pregnancy reduction. Fertility
and Sterility 64(1): 51-61.
CrossRef Menneskeverd. Tema: Abort.
https://www.menneskeverd.no/tema/abort/ Nasjonal behandlingstjeneste
for avansert invasiv fostermedisin. (2016).
Årsrapport.
https://forskningsprosjekter.ihelse.net/senter/rapport/NB- Nasjonal behandlingstjeneste
for avansert invasiv fostermedisin. (2017).
Årsrapport.
https://forskningsprosjekter.ihelse.net/senter/rapport/NB- Nilsen, L. (2016). Frykter
konsekvensene av fosterreduksjon. Dagens
Medisin.
https://www.dagensmedisin.no/artikler/2016/02/18/frykter- NOU 1991: 6. (1990). Mennesker
og bioteknologi. https://www.regjeringen.no/
Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons
and Persons. New York: Oxford
University Press. Pew Research Center. (2018). 6.
Religion and society.
http://www.pewforum.org/
2018/05/29/religion-and-society/ (Accessed
15.12.20). Retsinformation. (2006).
Vejledning om svangerskabsafbrydelse og
foster-reduktion, 3. Tilladelig
fosterreduktion.
https://www.retsinformation.dk/ Rognsvåg, S. & Weibye, T.
(2016). KrF og Sp ber Høie forby
tvillingaborter. Dagen. http://www.dagen.no/Nyheter/FOSTERREDUKSJON/KrF-og-Sp- Røe, K., Salvesen, K. Å. &
Eggebø, T. M. (2012). Blir retningslinjene
for fosterdiagnostisk ultralyd fulgt? Tidsskrift
for Den norske legeforening 132(14):
1603-6. Salvesen, K.Å. (2016).
Selvbestemt fosterreduksjon av tvillinger.
Dagens Medisin.
https://www.dagensmedisin.no/artikler/2016/04 Sampson, A. & Ch. De
Crespigny, L. (1992). Vanishing twins: the
frequency of spontaneous foetal reduction of
a twin pregnancy. Ultrasound in
Obstetrics & Gynecology 2(2):
107-109.
CrossRef Santana, D. S., Cecatti, J. G.,
Surita, F. G., Silveira C., Costa, M. L.,
Souza, J. P.,… Vogel, J. P. (2016) Twin
Pregnancy and Severe Maternal Outcomes: The
World Health Organization Multicountry
Survey on Maternal and Newborn Health. Obstetrics
& Gynecology 127(4): 631-641.
CrossRef Saugstad, O. D. (2016a).
Fosterreduksjon åpner for ekstrem sortering.
Morgenbladet.
https://morgenbladet.no/ideer/2016/02 Saugstad, O. D. (2016b).
Fosterreduksjon er inhumant.
Tvillingreduksjon åpner for ekstrem
sortering. Aftenposten
https://www.aftenposten.no/ Saugstad, O. D. (2018). Abort
og Verdier. Vårt Land.
http://www.verdidebatt.no/
innlegg/11729647-abort-og-verdier Schreiner-Engel, P., Walther,
V. N., Midnex, J., Lynch, L. &
Berkowitz, R. L. (1995). First-trimester
multifetal pregnancy reduction: Acute and
persistent psychologic reactions. American Journal
of Obstetrics & Gynecology 172(2):
541-547.
CrossRef Sentilhes, L., Audibert, F.,
Dommergues, M., Descamps, P., Frydman, R.,
Mahieu-Caputo, D. (2008). Multifetal
pregnancy reduction: indications, technical
aspects and psychological impact. La Presse
Médicale 37(2): 295-306.
CrossRef Skogedal, M. & Jemli, N.
(2017). Tvillinger langer ut mot
fosterreduksjon: Hvem av oss skal bort?
Stavanger Aftenblad.
https://www.byas.no/ aktuelt/i Skoli, S. (2016). Vi
tvillingmødre vet at våre tvillinger er
knyttet sammen på et nivå selv ikke vi kan
forstå. Dagen. https://www.dagen.no/
Solberg, E. (2018). Grensen mot
sorteringssamfunnet. Ernas blogg.
https://erna.no/2018/10/19/grensen-mot-sorteringssamfunnet/
Sosial- og helsedepartementet.
(2001). I-42/2001.
https://www.regjeringen.no/
no/dokumenter/i-422001/id108956 Statens medicinsk-etiska råd.
(2005). Yttrande angående s.k.
fosterreduktion.
http://www.smer.se/skrivelser/yttrande-angaende-s-kfosterreduktion- Statens medicinsk-etiska råd.
(2017). Reduktion av antal foster.
http://www.smer.se/smer-kommenterar/smer-kommenterar20171- Stone, J., Ferrara, L.,
Kamrath, J., Getrajdman, J., Berkowitz, R.,
Moshier, E., Eddleman, K. (2008).
Contemporary outcomes with the latest 1000
cases of multifetal pregnancy reduction
(MPR). American Journal of Obstetrics
& Gynecology 199(4): 406e1-406e4. Stotland, N. L. & Shrestha,
A. D. (2018). More Evidence That Abortion Is
Not Associated With Increased Risk of Mental
Illness. JAMA Psychiatry 75(8):
775-776.
CrossRef Sundhedsloven. (2005). Afsnit
VII Svangerskabsafbrydelse og
fosterreduktion kap. 25 og 26.
https://www.retsinformation.dk/
Forms/R0710.aspx? Sørvig, Ø.S. (2017). Jeg var
abortmotstander i ett år. Minerva.
https://www.minervanett.no/jeg-var-abortmotstander-ett-ar/
(12 November 2018). The New York Times. (2013). Abortion restrictions
in states. http://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2013/06/18/us/politics/abortion- Warren, M. A. (1973). On the moral and legal status of abortion. The Monist 57(1): 43-61. CrossRef Woollard, F. (2016). Motherhood
and Mistakes about Defeasible Duties to
Benefit. Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 97(1): 126-149.
CrossRef World Health Organization.
(1946). Constitution of WHO: Principles.
http://www.who.int/about/mission/en/
(Accessed 18 March 2018). Zemet, R., Haas, J., Bart, Y., Barzilay, E, Zloto, K., Hershenson, R. (…) Lipitz, S. 2018. 133: Pregnancy outcome after multifetal pregnancy reduction of triplets to twins versus reduction to singleton American Journal of Obstetrics & Gynecology, 218(1):94. CrossRef Østborg, T.B. (2016).
Prinsipper og følelser om fosterreduksjon.
Dagens Medisin.
https://www.dagensmedisin.no/artikler/2016/03/04/prinsipper-
|