Etikk i praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2020),
14(2),
1–7
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v14i2.3830
Leder
Introduction
Justice
of Others: Arbitrary Law-making in Contemporary Migration
Policy
Patricia Mindus
Does
the regulation of migration constitute a
blatant case of arbitrary law-making? What
is arbitrary law-making? And how does it
manifest itself in contemporary migration
policy? These are pressing issues that the
scholars who come together in this special
issue seek to engage with, by exploring
international migration from the point of
view of arbitrary power. When does
legitimate state discretion slide into an
exercise of arbitrary power? Since we cannot
address what we do not understand, the
urgency of the matter addressed in this
special issue speaks for itself.
Deciding
who may enjoy the right of abode, the
right to remain, the right to asylum and
to citizenship is a key power of the
state: it is a regal prerogative, an act
of sovereignty, limited only by
deliberately accepted commitments, such as
the respect for human rights. This makes
migration policy an exceptionally
interesting ground to test the limits of
discretion and the forms of arbitrariness.
Power can be understood to be of a
discretional nature if it acts freely
within the boundaries defined by law,
whereas arbitrariness qualifies
discretional power exceeding the limits of
law.
The special
issue is conversant both with the
details of the legal frameworks and the
theories involved, in contrast to much of
the literature on migration in the social
and economic sciences of a more general
character. As of today, little
or no conversation has arisen across the
domain of practical philosophy – ethics,
political theory, social philosophy or
philosophy of law – on arbitrary
law-making generally. We believe migration
law is a policy area that would be
interesting to focus on because of the
recurrent use of discretionary practices
in migration law and because of the
ethical issues raised by practices
conceived to be arbitrary. Arbitrary law-making
has yet to garner the attention it
deserves as a key concern in relation to
migration law. Arbitrariness is
thus not only under-theorised but also
lacks sufficient empirical analysis.
The special issue covers both
fronts by presenting a conceptual analysis
of arbitrary law-making that sets out to
typify its various meanings, along an
empirical account of its actual
functioning in legal and political
practice. As arbitrariness becomes a
pressing concern for lawyers, politicians
and scholars attempting to grasp the
discretionary powers of judicial and
administrative authorities vis-a-vis legal
subjects, its social impact as well as its
political consequences must be taken into
consideration in order to fully comprehend
how central arbitrariness has become for a
philosophical and a sociological account
of law-making. Migration policy is
precisely where arbitrariness vividly
shows its face, and where its various
forms unleash their most revealing
implications. It is in this field that we
must dig further if we want to know how
this hitherto peripheral and surrogated
dimension of legal decision-making
stretches the leeway of legal officials to
the very margin of legality, disclosing
the social tension and the power struggle
between their agency and the structures
that condition and enable it.
The special
issue
– entitled “Justice of Others: Arbitrary
Law-making in Contemporary Migration
Policy” – therefore brings scholars, both
junior and senior, from a broad range of
disciplines into conversation over
migration policy and migration law. This
interdisciplinary approach is called for:
on this topic narrow research agendas,
often blind to what is going on in
methodologically diverse yet substantially
contiguous fields of inquiry, still
dominate. This is an attempt to overcome
this limitation of the state of the art.
The first steps towards this special issue
were taken at a U4 conference at the
University of Uppsala a few years ago and
the issue been brought to completion
largely thanks to funding generously
offered by the Knut & Alice
Wallenberg Foundation (grant KAW
2014.0133).
In general, the internal
organisation of this special issue follows
the format of an increased granularity: as
your reading moves along, the articles go
from the theoretically focused more
general aspects to investigating the more
specific and concrete manifestations of
arbitrary law-making in contemporary
migration policy.
Patricia Mindus (professor in
practical philosophy, Uppsala University,
Sweden) starts off with an article that
purports to establish a move ‘Towards a Theory of Arbitrary
Law-making in Migration Policy’ and which serves as a
thematic introduction to the topic of
arbitrary law-making. The article
considers what arbitrary law-making is and
what may count as arbitrary law-making in
the field of migration policy. It
contributes to the discussion of arbitrary
law-making in relation to migration policy
in two ways. First, it offers an analysis
of arbitrariness, points out that
rhetorical definitions of the term abound
– perhaps unsurprisingly given that
migration is a highly-contested policy
area – and argues for why transposing a
conception developed in ethical theory to
the law has high theoretical costs; an
alternative conception is described and
found to be better equipped to deal with
arbitrary law-making in migration policy.
It is argued that if we want to understand
how arbitrariness plays out in the field
of migration law – which is necessary to
find ways to hinder its spread by the
adoption of specific law-making practices
– we first need to distinguish
arbitrariness from legitimate choices of
legislators. Secondly, a typology of forms
of arbitrariness is fleshed out in
relation to contemporary migration policy.
The policy area is here broadly construed
to include not only naturalisation
processes, but also migration, asylum and
refugee policies and more generally border
control. The examples are taken from a
broad selection of countries. They have
been chosen for illustrative purposes
only. A key point of the article is to
explore the meaning of arbitrariness as
applied to an authority, illustrating
embodiments of the different meanings of
the term to be found in contemporary
citizenship and migration policies. The
conceptual unpacking of arbitrariness that
it undertakes clears the ground for a
proper conceptual understanding of
arbitrary law-making, but also for a
comprehensive knowledge of how it
functions in legal practice and political
reality. The paper thus enables a
differentiation among types of
arbitrariness that can either constitute
forms of illegal practices, irrational
policies or discriminatory statuses.
Differentiation is paramount to developing
ways of reducing the arbitrary rule of
public officials in migration and
citizenship policies, which makes this
article an essential preliminary
conceptualisation of the key problematic
of this special issue.
We then go in medias res.
A longstanding critical voice in migration
ethics, Phil Cole (Senior
Lecturer in Politics and International
Relations
at UWE
Bristol, UK) contributes with the article
entitled ‘Framing the
Refugee’ and looks at the power of
representation of liberal political theory
with regard to refugees. In his view,
legal and political arbitrariness lie in
representing refugees as lacking agency.
His key point is that liberalism fails to
conceive of refugees as politically
capable actors and is hence complicit in
the arbitrary neutralisation of their
emancipatory potential and participatory
powers. This paper emphasises the moral
justifiability of that state of affairs by
seeking some answers to the question as to
why liberal political theory construes a
concept of the refugee that does not
contain any element of political agency.
Most obviously, Cole acknowledges that
refugees do perform a significant social
role in contemporary societies and are
hence active members in them. Nonetheless,
they remain neglected in their political
role by most political theory. What
does it mean to have political agency for
Phil Cole? It means to have the power of
self-representation, that is, of being
allowed and even enabled by a given legal
system to bring about change in the
political order, or at least to
participate in that change.
But Cole also addresses the
role of ‘theory’ in calling attention to
this downside of the contemporary liberal
democratic order. Theory becomes even more
crucial at times of urgency, that is,
times where theorists are called upon
their moral responsibility to deepen their
philosophical imagination as Hannah Arendt
so forcefully underlined. The theoretical
task of ‘re-framing’ the Refugee
entails reconfiguring political philosophy
and its traditional categories of
sovereignty, citizenship and nationality.
The liberal inability to accommodate
political agency of many members of the
political community – especially of
non-nationals – is a sign of the
historical contingency of the current
rules of political membership and makes
evident the imperative of rethinking
politics in ways that avoid the
arbitrariness of treatment and aim instead
at equality and justice. If political
leaders can re-write the rules of
membership to suit their own ideological
agendas, the same requirement should be
addressed by – indeed demanded of –
political and legal theorists.
This is not, however, as easy
as it seems, according to Phil Cole. In
his view, political theory is confronted
with fundamental
challenges, the most obvious of them being
that ‘theory’ is usually unequipped to
defeat its own ‘topology’. Note that in
saying this Cole is raising a more
pressing concern about arbitrary
law-making: it may be that arbitrariness –
especially the arbitrary treatment of
aliens by the sovereign state and by
liberal democracies in particular – is
inscribed in the very DNA of liberalism.
No matter how odd this may seem, Cole
advances the view that ideas, however
creative of a new order, or transformative
of a given status quo, never
appear in ‘free form’, and are instead
deeply rooted in a structure that
constrains our imagination. The challenge
is thus to develop a meta-theory in which
the very way in which marginalised sectors
of society – such as the ‘poor’ – are
framed by liberal political theory, can be
re-conceptualised as a product of an
international economic order that robs
those sectors of their agency as the very
condition of its internal functioning. We
must therefore question how the very idea
of the refugee is produced, for it
symbolises the construction of an inside
and an outside that is complicit with the
arbitrary play of legal status involved in
migration policy. Cole’s main point
regarding this is that certain groups get
sidelined by economic, political and
social systems because they are already
excluded from theoretical systems to start
with.
The
next article moves into the area of
political theory and migration law. The
well-known scholar on territoriality and
immigrants’ rights, Linda Bosniak (Distinguished
Professor of Law at Rutgers,
USA)
contributes with an article entitled Territorial
Presence as a Ground For Claims: Some
Reflections where she returns to
political theory to assess the moral and
legal position of those individuals who
are inside the territory of liberal
democratic states, but whose very presence
has not been authorised by the state. She
poses the question as to what their
physical presence means and does from a
political perspective. The article is part
of a broader political phenomenology of
territoriality in liberal national thought
and emphasises the idea that migrants’
physical presence within the state’s
territory lies at the analytical heart of
the conversation about irregular
immigrants. What is paradoxical about the
territorial presence of unauthorized
migrants is that such presence is
simultaneously (1) the source of the
offence that states invoke as a
justification for making them ‘illegal’;
(2) the basis for basic fair treatment
protections the migrants may claim from
the state while present; and (3) the
ground for claims they make (or that are
made on their behalf) to remain – i.e., to
stay in the territory. Territorial
presence is thus fertile ground for
analysing arbitrary law-making in
migration. Bosniak sets out to analyse
some recent legal developments pertaining
to the governance of irregular noncitizen
immigrants in the United States. These
developments bear on the project of
theorising "immigrant justice" as
resistance to the growing illiberalisation
of migration policy. In Bosniak’s view,
the very existence of a class of people
designated as irregular migrants within
state polities presupposes that such
polities maintain formal exclusionary
border regimes and that in such regimes,
some persons are predesignated as
ineligible for entry. And even though
those exclusion rules do not function to
fully preclude entry and presence of such
persons, states do not treat their arrival
as an automatic basis for full membership
either. Hence, irregular immigrants are
territorially present in a state that
purports to eschew that presence. She then
explores how the idea of “sanctuary”
relates to the kinds of claims that both
liberal humanitarians and immigrant
justice advocates have been making over
the last few years. These are claims which
ground protection in what exponents cite
as the overriding ethical significance of
immigrants’ territorial presence – their already-hereness
– as the basis for recognition and rights.
In particular, Bosniak makes the
convincing case that even though
"sanctuary" provides a logic of safe
harbour, it fails to end the predicament
of constitutive exclusionism based on
borders, and thus it fails to end the
predicament of inequality of treatment
that these immigrants have actually
inherited. For her, the political, social,
but also philosophical, struggle for the
idea of border abolitionism, she
maintains, requires a figurative sword
that must go beyond sanctuary so that
borders are not just mitigated, but
radically deconstructed and even
destroyed. She takes this to be the vital
imperative that confronts all legal and
political theorists who must engage the
normative challenge of rethinking
arbitrary law-making in view of the new
inequalities that a global political order
grounded on sovereign borders produces.
The
critical tonality is pursued also in the
next article, albeit with a focus on legal
theory and some aspects of it that are
connected to the institutionalist theory
of law, an important continental 20th
century legacy, that is seldom highlighted
in relation to contemporary dividing
issues such as migration. Conversant
with
both philosophy of law and migration
law, Enrica Rigo (associate professor in
legal and social theory at the Department
of Law, University of Roma Tre,
Italy) contributes with an
article on Arbitrary Law Making and
Unorderable Subjectivities in Legal
Theoretical Approaches to Migration.
She considers the
changes that have affected European border
regimes of migration control as a test
case for discussing arbitrariness. Her
argument highlights the limited capacity
of notions of arbitrariness – defined as a
departure from the rule of law – to
capture the ongoing conflict at the
borders of Europe and instead brings the
ambivalent meaning of arbitrariness to the
fore. By comparing Santi Romano’s
classical theory of legal pluralism with
recent analyses of legal globalisation
processes, she is able to show how
arbitrariness emerges either as an
authoritative attempt to impose a
different order on society or as a means
to contrast acts of resistance to border
regimes. In both cases, arbitrariness
forcefully blurs the limits between the
ordered and unordered. By her analysis,
this indicates the paradoxical
impossibility of excluding what is outside
the law from the legal order. On this
basis, Rigo advocates for the importance
of reframing the demand for open borders
as an appeal to liberty by those who
challenge the pragmatic order of migration
regimes. Indeed, as Rigo points out,
arbitrariness is necessarily limited when
the legal order recognises, at least to
some extent, the agency and the claims of
subjectivities that resist the dichotomy
between inclusion and exclusion.
The steady focus on
how legal constraints are being played out
in certain social settings takes us to the
next article, authored by Alexis Spire (Director of
research at the CNRS, France). A sociologist with a
longstanding interest in inequalities,
Spire refers to a very interesting
ethnographic study of the visa service at
the French consulate in Tunis and reflects
on arbitrariness, using this first-hand
experience as his starting point. He develops the
thesis, grounded in sociology, that
discretionary power works, as suggested by
the title of his article, as a political
weapon against foreigners. Spire shows how
the administrative practices of officials
who process the admission of immigrants
show significant variability in how
migration policy is enforced on the
ground. For him, inequality of treatment
lies in the very hierarchy of tasks and
services of what he dubs, following Pierre
Bourdieu, the immigration "field". This
social field is profoundly unequal in that
it empowers legal officials by not
providing foreigners with the necessary
means to resist or syndicate the
arbitrariness of administrative
procedures. According to Spire, this is
because the governments’ security
priorities favour suspicion towards
foreigners that the media then reinforces,
thus authorising so-called street-level
bureaucrats to act with great leeway
toward immigrants. Under pressure,
governments implement what the author
calls a "trompe-l’oeil policy" that
explores the ambivalence between
international and domestic law: while the
state enforces repressive laws that
apparently comply with fundamental human
rights, it leaves to low-ranking civil
servants enough discretion to make those
rights ineffective. This point is Spire’s
central contention. The arbitrariness of
these officials is neither contingent nor
accidental: it actually constitutes a
deliberate "frontline policy" to increase
the discretionary power of street-level
bureaucrats in charge of regulating
admissions. Unequal treatment comes in
three flavours in this context. First,
officials are asked to ensure that each
right granted to a foreigner will not
threaten the national order, meaning the
economic, social and political order. They
are therefore in a position to judge the
suitability of each application in view of
their own arbitrary interpretation of what
such a "threat" consists of. The question
of discretionary power is in this way
intimately linked to the problem of
equality in front of the law. Second, the
scarcity of material and human resources
allocated to services in charge of
welcoming migrants starkly contrasts with
the expenditure incurred to deport
foreigners. Inequality also arises from
how agents perceive users and the leeway
they have to implement the law. Third,
inequality is related to the abilities and
means foreigners have to challenge
discretionary power, especially through
their use of legal tools or legal
intermediaries. Spire thus concludes that
such "frontline policy" has increasingly
been used as a weapon against migrants,
especially since the early 2000s, when
immigration and detention policies were
generalised in France. More broadly, in
Europe as well as in United States,
immigration reforms have made greater use
of detention and focused on enforcement
rather than on hosting programmes and
services for asylum seekers. But they have
also strengthened the role of legal
intermediaries. Hence the need to
investigate how discretionary power is
challenged as it sheds light on the power
relationship between states and migrants.
The contribution that
closes this special issue is authored by
Francesca Asta (PhD, University of Roma
Tre, Italy). It is entitled Arbitrary
Decision-making and the Rule of Law: The
Role of the Jurisdiction in Migrants’
Detention Proceedings – Between
Discretion and Arbitrariness. The starting point is that
while many studies have highlighted
substantial "bureaucracy domination" in
procedures relating to migrants’ access to
territory, little attention has been
devoted to the arbitrariness of judicial
decisions or to the judicial role in
general in the numerous proceedings that
increasingly affect migrants. Asta’s study
focuses on the Italian case law in
expulsion and detention proceedings of
irregular third country national citizens
and asylum seekers. In here article, she
presents the results from her qualitative
empirical study on decisions issued by the
competent national authorities. The data
was analysed based on a selection of
theoretical tools, all referable to the
general concept of the rule of law. The
judicial decisions on pre-removal
detention proceedings are examined in two
case studies: the jurisprudence on
detention of irregular migrants, in
different offices of the Justice of the
Peace in Italy; and the case law on
detention of asylum seekers in the
Ordinary Tribunal of Rome. The assumption
underlying the research is that various
conceptions of the rule of law may have
different explanatory power when it comes
to making sense of what is going on in the
everyday practice of legal officials.
Through a historical-conceptual analysis,
Asta lists six theoretical models of the
rule of law in the Western tradition of
political and legal thought, and assesses
their explanatory power against the
backdrop of the data collected.
Highlighting the benefits and drawbacks of
each explanatory framework, she concludes
that, first, the results of the two cases
studies cannot be fully explained by any
single model available in the literature.
This fact alone casts doubts on the
explanatory power that these theories may
be said to have and calls for further
research on judicial decision-making more
generally. Secondly, concerning discretion
and arbitrariness, she finds that the
judicial approach which assures the
highest protection of rights is also the
one that is most easily influenced by
arbitrariness. She argues that this
apparent paradox may be resolved with
reference to the plural dimensions of
arbitrariness. If we consider
arbitrariness from a legal point of view,
as an illegal decision, it is unsurprising
that the authority that uses its
discretionary power the most is also the
one most likely to abuse its power. But if
we consider arbitrariness from the
philosophical-political point of view, as
a form of domination characterised by the
absence of sufficient justification, it
becomes clear that self-image matters a
lot in explaining the risk of falling into
arbitrary choices. The authority most
likely to stretch its discretionary power
into the realm of arbitrariness is thus
the one that also assures the highest
protection of rights: this authority views
its own role as the guardian of
fundamental rights and of the
constitutional democratic legal order. The
risk of exercising its power in
criticisable ways increases with the
stakes of the choices the authority makes.
This contrasts with an authority that
views itself merely as a rubberstamp in
line with the requirements of the law
enforcement agencies, where the risks of
arbitrariness, but also the authority’s
ability to protect migrant rights, are
more circumscribed.
This special issue set out to
achieve two objectives. First, it shows the
importance of meeting across areas of
expertise in discussing ethically and
politically sensitive issues like migration
and arbitrary power exercises. By bringing
together scholars with an interest in the
problematic aspects of law-making in the
area of migration policy, the hope is to
shed light on an area of inquiry – arbitrary
law-making in migration policy – that has
hitherto not received the attention it
deserves and is often not addressed with the
full toolkit and due methodological wealth.
The special issue, in this sense, represents
an interdisciplinary meeting ground. Second,
we aim to contribute to the understanding of
how and why arbitrary and discretionary
practices in the field of migration law come
into being. Some of these practices are
illustrated in the following articles.
Hopefully this special issue will contribute
to opening up fertile research venues for
applied ethics at the crossroads of social,
political and legal theory.