Etikk i praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2020),
14(1),
1–6
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v14i1.3583
Leder
Introduction
Emergency,
Values and Evidence: How Applied Ethics Can Help in Making
Very Difficult Decisions
Allen Alvarez, Espen Dyrnes Stabell, May
Thorseth
This
first issue of Etikk i praksis –
Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics
for the year 2020 comes out amidst the
havoc caused by the global spread of
COVID-19. The outbreak started in
Wuhan, China on December 12, 2019
(Peng Zhou et al. 2020) and has
infected millions after five months of
rapid spreading. Societies around the
world implemented quarantine measures
and public health interventions – such
as safe physical distancing, closing
schools, churches and places where the
public could gather – in order to slow
down transmission of the new
coronavirus SARS-CoV-2. The World
Health Organization declared it a
global pandemic on the 12th
of March 2020. The growing number of
cases caused by the new coronavirus
threatened to overwhelm healthcare
systems, so it became urgent to slow
down transmission to a level that was
within the capacity of those systems.
Quarantine measures suppressed the
surge but still many lives were lost.
These measures unavoidably slowed down
economic activity, and many lost their
jobs as businesses were forced to
close down. The price of oil plunged
and stock markets were pummelled. Many
big cities that used to be choked by
extreme pollution have experienced
unprecedented clean air. Flights
around the world were brought to a
virtual halt. The world did not avoid
flying to slow down pollution as
environmental activists like Greta
Thunberg urged many to do for the sake
of future generations. Air travel
stopped instead for the urgent reason
of slowing down the spread of
COVID-19.
Slowing down the spread of SARS-CoV-2
is undeniably the most urgent health
emergency that the world has acted on
since the last global influenza
pandemic of 1918-1919 killed at least
50 million people and infected 500
million worldwide (U.S. Centers for
Disease Control and Prevention 2020).
It is of imminent importance to
prevent avoidable illness, suffering
and deaths due to COVID-19. Public
health strategies are necessary to
prevent surges and the further spread
of the new coronavirus. While some
measures remain controversial, such as
the decision in many countries to
close down schools even for the
smallest children, some degree of
isolation and quarantine, social
distancing measures such as gathering
bans, the cancellation of public
events, and restricted transportation
seem strictly necessary (Hastings
Center 2020).
On the other hand, drastic measures to
stop the spread of the virus may have
serious negative impacts, for instance
by slowing the economy and causing
massive unemployment. In
Norway, the unemployment rate in
March reached 14.7%. The rate
compares to 2.3% in the month
before, and is the highest recorded
unemployment rate in the country
(Solsvik 2020). On March 19, the
Bank of America “officially
declared” that the US economy had
fallen into depression (Stevens
2020).
In Sweden, almost 14,000 employees
were given redundancy notice between
March 16 and 22, which compares to
just over 3,000 for the whole month
of March 2019 (Arbetsförmedlingen
2020). These are just a few examples
of how national economies are
affected by the virus and the
measures taken against it. The most
dramatic consequences, however, are
likely to be felt by poorer
countries (Harvey 2020, WFP 2020),
and the long-term impacts on the
national and global economies have
yet to be seen.
The challenges of isolation and
working from home that is required by
the quarantine measures can also
affect mental health. Protecting
people’s psychological well-being is
very important, but the risks of
quarantine may be necessary in order
to protect our healthcare systems and
prevent the avoidable deaths that
could result if the system collapses
from an uncontrolled surge.
Viewing health and economic
considerations as competing concerns
is ethically problematic. Still, we
sometimes have to triage them, for
example when economic considerations
prevent us from offering equal
treatment to all, or when shorter term
public health and safety measures have
long-term effects on economic activity
(which might in turn affect the health
and well-being of present and future
people). Deciding which of the
competing concerns to give more weight
to is not an easy choice. The field of
applied ethics has generated a number
of tools for making reasoned choices
between competing values, such as
conceptual analysis, critical
reasoning and moral evaluation. We may
analyse what reciprocity means or
specify what harm is when we talk
about balancing harms and benefits;
examine what evidence is required to
establish claims about effectiveness
of quarantine measures; or discuss
what it means to trade off essential
goods such as the freedom to publicly
gather in groups without following
infection control measures in place to
protect life and health. Using the
tools of applied ethics requires
sensitivity to facts and attention to
the best evidence available. This may
also require taking reasonable
precautions when the risks are great
despite the absence of definitive
evidence.
The nature of the public health
emergency brought about by the global
COVID-19 pandemic has shifted the
value focus of healthcare
professionals from patient-centred
considerations of respect for
individual autonomy to that of social
justice and concern for fairness in
the distribution of risks and
benefits. The classic harm principle
that limits individual liberty directs
healthcare providers to reasonably
restrict patient’s freedom when this
freedom threatens harm to others. A
patient showing symptoms of COVID-19
must self-isolate even if it is
against her preference. In a similar
manner, public health officers are
legally empowered by their societies
to impose restrictions on individuals
to move freely for the sake of
preventing harm to the collective,
including to the individual whose
movement is restricted.
Healthcare professionals in hospitals
around the world that have experienced
the greatest surge of COVID-19 cases
faced tragic decisions in triaging
sick patients. When the number of
staff, personal protective equipment
(PPE), medicines and medical devices
are less than the number of patients
needing treatment, these care
providers have to make difficult
decisions (Frakt 2020) that may cause
them moral distress (White & Lo
2020).
It is for this reason that applied
ethicists need to go beyond merely
practising impassioned reasoning in
addressing the challenges of ethical
decision-making in a pandemic.
Ethicists who are equipped with
interdisciplinary knowledge and skills
need to engage the virtues of
compassion, courage and integrity.
Healthcare ethicists have the
opportunity to provide moral distress
support to their traumatized clinical
colleagues in addition to providing
expert ethical decision-making
guidance and policy advice (Hamric
& Epstein 2017). Academic
ethicists have the opportunity to help
untangle conceptual and logical
confusion amidst the chaos of the
pandemic.
The need for making careful,
evidence-based ethical decisions is
particularly acute as societies plan
to reopen following months of
quarantine and restricted economic
activities. Among other essential
things, there must be clear evidence
that sufficient testing, effective
contact tracing measures, supported
self-isolation and healthcare system
readiness are in place to allow
reopening safely (Allen et al. 2020).
If these essential safety measures are
not ready it would be unethical, if
not reckless, to reopen. We can employ
the decision tools of conceptual
analysis, critical reasoning about
values and evidence, and moral
evaluation in making these difficult
decisions collectively and with
sufficient stakeholder
engagement.
This open issue of the Nordic Journal
of Applied Ethics consists of four
papers that discuss topics covering
vaccination, sustainability,
development ethics research and family
ethics.
The first article of the issue is
entitled Mandatory childhood
vaccination: Should Norway follow?
In the article, Espen Gamlund, Karl
Erik Müller, Kathrine Knarvik Paquet,
and Carl Tollef Solberg discuss
whether Norway should follow countries
such as France and Italy in making
their childhood vaccination programmes
mandatory. The authors give a brief
history of vaccines and the current
Norwegian childhood vaccination
programme, and then go on to discuss
the most central arguments against
mandatory childhood vaccination: the
argument from the standpoints of
parental rights, bodily integrity,
naturalness, mistrust and immunisation
coverage. Next, they examine the
central arguments in favour of
mandatory childhood vaccination from
the standpoints of harm, herd immunity
and as a precautionary strategy. The
paper concludes that there are
convincing moral arguments in favour
of adopting a policy of mandatory
childhood vaccination in Norway.
In the second article, Staying
within planetary boundaries as a
premise for sustainability: On the
responsibility to address
counteracting sustainable
development goals, Heidi
Rapp Nilsen takes a fresh look at
this well-known concept of
sustainability. Nilsen adopts the
framing of environment, society and
economy and notes the widely
acknowledged claim that
environmental sustainability is
essential to establishing societal
and economic sustainability. This
paper addresses the gap in
discussions about the competing
dynamics between these three
sustainability pillars and the
assumed connection between them
expressed in the sustainable
development goals of the United
Nations. By conceptual analysis, the
reinforcing links, as well as
competing goals, of these three
kinds of sustainability are
explored. Examples of how to apply
the proposed method of analysis on
research and development at
different levels are presented, such
as on the level of project
development at the global level of
the United Nations. The main goal of
the discussion is to motivate
responsibility in tracking the
timing and manner in which
competition between sustainability
goals occurs. The author proposes to
do this by identifying specific ways
the global ecological system
boundaries are violated together
with the harms that result from
trading off environmental
sustainability. Another proposed
step is drawn from the guidance
provided by the Norwegian National
Research Ethics Committee, which
proposes the inclusion of research
findings about how planetary
boundaries are breached and the
damaging effects of such breaches on
human safety.
In the third article, Using
Insights in Sen’s Capability
Approach to Overcome Design and
Execution Challenges in Empirical
Development Ethics Research,
Almas Mazigo & Johan Hattingh
discuss how Sen’s capability approach
(CA) can offer helpful guidance to
development ethicists in the design
and execution of empirical methods in
development ethics research. This
demonstrates another example of how
empirical methods can be combined with
ethical reflection (Alvarez 2001).
Engagement with relevant stakeholders
fills the information gap about the
assumptions we make regarding what
these stakeholders may believe or
value. The reflections on and
assessments of stakeholders’ actual
individual and collective values,
capacities, roles and interests in the
fisheries sector in Tanzania’s Ukerewe
District contribute to understanding
the context and are an example of how
stakeholder engagement enriches
ethical analysis. These stakeholders
are better positioned to unpack the
nature and causes of the poverty of
small-scale fishers and what is
required to overcome these deficits.
The stakeholders improve their
understanding of the cause and
prevalence of institutional and
professional apathy towards poverty,
and collaborate on what they think
should be done to address the
challenges small-scale fishers face.
Empirical data enhance the moral
reflection by enabling robust
theorising about the changes that can
be made to alleviate this specific
type of poverty and about the relevant
ethical reflection appropriate for
guiding future actions to reduce
poverty and increase the wellbeing of
fishing communities in the Ukerewe
District.
Finally, Marcus William Hunt, in his
article What
grounds special treatment between
siblings?, proposes a theory of
why siblings ought to treat one
another in ways that they need not
treat others. The paper begins by
presenting intuitive judgments about
how siblings ought to treat one
another – for example, that they ought
to have relationships with each
other’s children, provide financial
aid in certain situations, and offer
advice to one another about various
aspects of their lives. The author
then discusses three theories that
might explain the judgments, adapted
from the literature on filial piety:
the gratitude theory, the friendship
theory, and the special goods theory.
He argues that these theories fail to
explain some of the central intuitive
judgments. He proposes instead a familial
belonging theory, which starts
with the idea that the institution of
the family has certain goals that
impose normative demands on family
members. It is suggested that one such
goal is that every member feel
familial belonging towards every other
member – a goal which according to the
author grounds the ways in which
siblings ought to treat one another
specially.
This issue includes Espen Dyrnes
Stabell’s review of the recently
published book Finance or Food?
The Role of Cultures, Values and
Ethics in Land Use Negotiations,
edited by Hilde Bjørkhaug, Philip
McMichael and Bruce Muirhead. Toronto:
University of Toronto Press.
We have written this editorial
introduction from our respective homes
while observing quarantine measures,
fully aware of the need to do our part
to protect our communities. We express
our heartfelt appreciation to our first
responders for their sacrifices and
remember those we have lost from
COVID-19. We are committed to continue
publishing peer-reviewed research in
applied ethics to support our societies
with useful knowledge during this
pandemic as our global societies address
this terrible viral outbreak. Many
thanks to our contributing authors,
expert reviewers, editorial staff, board
of editors and copyeditors. Stay strong
as we are all in this together.
References
Alvarez, A. A. (2001). How
rational should bioethics be? The value of
empirical approaches. Bioethics,
15(5‐6), 501-519. Crossref
Frakt, Austin (2020). Who Should
Be Saved First? Experts Offer Ethical
Guidance The New York Times. March 24, 2020.
Available at https://www.nytimes.com/
2020/03/24/upshot/coronavirus-
rationing-decisions-ethicists.html
Allen, D., Block, S., Cohen,
J….(2020). Roadmap to Pandemic
Resilience: Massive Scale Testing,
Tracing, and Supported Isolation (TTSI) as
the Path to Pandemic Resilience for a Free
Society. Edmond J. Safra Center for
Ethics, Harvard University. 56 pages.
Available online:
https://ethics.harvard.edu/covid-roadmap.
Date accessed: May 10, 2020.
Hamric, A. B., & Epstein, E.
G. (2017). A health system-wide moral
distress consultation service: development
and evaluation. HEC Forum 29:
2:127-143. Crossref
Harvey, F. (2020, April 21).
Coronavirus crisis could double number of
people suffering acute hunger – UN.
Available at:
https://www.theguardian.com/world/2020/apr/21/global-hunger-
could-be-next-big-impact-of-coronavirus-pandemic.
Date accessed: May 3, 2020.
Hastings Center (2020). Pandemics:
The Ethics of Mandatory and Voluntary
Interventions. Available at:
https://www.thehastingscenter.
org/briefingbook/ pandemic/ Date accessed:
May 10, 2020.
Solsvik,
T. (2020, April 3). Norway’s unemployment
soars to record of 14.7%. Reuters.
Available at: https://www.reuters.com/article
/health-coronavirus-norway-unemployment/norways-
unemployment-soars-to-record-14-7-of-work-force-idUSS8N2BJ039.
Date accessed: May 3, 2020
Stevens,
P. (2020, March 19). Bank of America says
recession is already here. CNBC.
Available online: https://www.cnbc.com/2020/03
/19/bank-of-america-says-the-recession-is-already-here-jobs-will-
be-lost-wealth-will-be-destroyed.htmlDate
accessed: March 20, 2020, from
U.S.
Centers
for Disease Control and Prevention (2020). 1918
Pandemic (H1N1 virus). Available
online: https://www.cdc.gov/flu/pandemic-
resources/1918-pandemic-h1n1.html. Date
accessed: May 10, 2020.
WFP
(2020).
2020 – Global Report on Food Crisis.
Retrieved May 3, 2020, from https://www.wfp.org/publications/2020-global-report-
food-crises.
White,
D. B., & Lo, B. (2020). A Framework for
Rationing Ventilators and Critical Care Beds
During the COVID-19 Pandemic. JAMA.Crossref
Zhou,
P., Yang, X. L., Wang, X. G., Hu, B., Zhang,
L., Zhang, W., ... & Chen, H. D. (2020).
A pneumonia outbreak associated with a new
coronavirus of probable bat origin. Nature,
579(7798), 270-273. Crossref