Etikk i praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2018),
12(2), 7-9
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v12i2.2868
Introduction to Open Section papers
Obligations in public
philosophical discourse
Allen Alvarez, May Thorseth & Siri
Granum Carson
Four
papers are included in the Open Section of this
November 2018 special issue. In the first paper
by Bjørn Hofmann and Siri Granum Carson entitled
Filosofiens rolle i det offentlige
ordskiftet: Hvordan har debatten om
sorteringssamfunnet i 2017 påvirket forholdet
mellom filosofi og samfunn? En innholdsanalyse
(The role of philosophy in public debate - A
content analysis of the debate on the "sorting
society" in Norway in 2017), the authors address
the recent increase of attention that philosophy
and ethics have gained in Norwegian media. They
point to the need to prevent philosophy from
becoming a new form of sophism ("art of
deception") by adhering to the ideals of the
profession that uphold making our claims,
perspectives, arguments, and conclusions clear
and comprehensible, and the willingness to
revise or withdraw these claims if clarity and
comprehensibility are not achieved. This call to
professional integrity was sparked by what the
authors observed as a tendency to adapt
philosophy to media discourse, which
inadvertently eliminates academic reservations
and nuances. In particular, they worry about the
trend of neglecting hidden assumptions, lack of
consistency, conceptual and evaluative
uncertainties, as well as ignorance of empirical
premises, counter-arguments and important
implications. They warn that these gaps in
public discourse could result in poorer public
debate, an impoverished society, and a weakened
reputation for philosophy as a discipline. They
apply these warnings based on a content analysis
of the Norwegian debate on "the
differentiation/sorting society" (sorteringssamfunnet),
initiated by Aksel Braanen Sterri's statement in
connection with the issue of introducing
non-invasive prenatal screening (NIPT) that
persons with Down syndrome cannot live full
lives. The authors welcome the impact of that
debate to the revival of public interest in
philosophical discussions, uncovering unspoken
intuitions and stimulating improved reasoning in
the public realm, but they warn that public
provocation through the media needs to be
balanced by analytic restraint as espoused by
the Socratic tradition in philosophy, lest we
succumb to a new sophism.
In
the second paper Provokativ offentlig
filosofi (Provocative Public
Philosophy), Aksel Braanen Sterri responds to
Bjørn Hofmann and Siri Granum Carson’s call
for restraint and argues that it is
inappropriate for epistemic and ethical
reasons. Sterri claims that contrary to the
criticism that provocative public philosophy
is harmful, imperialistic, erodes trust in
philosophers and creates too much (or
unnecessary) noise, well meaning public
philosophers do and should challenge consensus
and delve into issues that stir emotions to
promote clarity of thought. These two articles
in this special November issue of Etikk i
praksis remind us of the long-standing
metadebate about how philosophers should
engage the public and media. They revive the
discussion on how inclusive we should be of
diverse issues, as well as on approaches to
public deliberation of these diverse issues.
Should we ban certain forms of reasoning that
are identified with specific ideologies
because they seem to threaten the ideals of
neutrality or objectivity that protects the
integrity of public discourse (Alvarez 2014)?
Or should we promote a more open and inclusive
discussion that engages even topics or methods
that some may consider ‘harmful’ to public
discourse (Thorseth 2006)? Tolerating the
discomfort of including deliberative
approaches or potentially offensive taboo
topics in order to avoid marginalizing these
topics, so that their adherents do not resort
to harmful outlets if they are not allowed to
vent in public, has now become an all too
familiar dilemma in our current political
climate. It is timely to continue discussing
these metadebates to enhance our understanding
of how to responsibly engage the public.
In the third paper in the Open
Section, Steinar Bøyum’s The
Democratic Duty to Educate Oneself
presents an argument that democratic citizens
have a duty to educate themselves politically.
It turns the locus of responsibility for
political education from the all too common
agency of public intellectuals and political
philosophers to individual members of the
public. This discussion is another apt piece in
our troubled times of distressing politics.
Bøyum establishes a case for the moral
importance of individual competence for voting
and maintains that the substantial content of
the required competence must remain open. His
interesting analysis is a welcome contribution
to a constructive, if not politically
therapeutic, practical way forward in overcoming
the worries that election results around the
world indicate a declining competence among
electorates in choosing the right leaders and
making all-important decisions that impact their
collective wellbeing. Bøyum’s assessment of
Jason Brennan's idea of epistocracy merits a
closer look. The notion of the right to a
competent electorate, its validity and the
corresponding modest duty to educate oneself
politically (without the need for legal
reinforcement) is a must-read if we want to
carry on with society’s democratic project.
Readers are encouraged to reflectively engage in
this timely discussion towards a more
constructive and therapeutic approach to our
troubled political times.
Finally, Jonas Jakobsen and Kjersti
Fjørtoft’s In defence
of moderate Inclusivism: Revisiting Rawls and
Habermas concludes this issue's Open
Section with another interesting and related
discussion. The authors revisit the debate on
inclusivism specific to religious reasons. After
reviewing Rawls' and Habermas' theories of
deliberative democracy that focus on the
question of religious reasons in political
discourse, they identify that Rawls and Habermas
both defend what Jakobsen and Fjørtoft call a
“fully inclusivist” view of using religious
reasons in deliberations in the 'informal public
sphere'. Jakobsen and Fjørtoft then defend what
they call a “moderately inclusivist” view that
only requires a 'conversational translation
proviso' where citizens' duty to supplement
religious with proper political arguments is
only required if they are asked by their
co-discussants to do so. This is an interesting
update to what Bohman and other authors have
explored in previous discussions regarding the
role of what can be considered “private” reasons
in public debate (Bohman 1995).
Acknowledgments We
would like to
thank the
guest editors
for their work
on this
Special Issue
of the Nordic
Journal of
Applied
Ethics. We
express our
gratitude to
the
contributors
to the Open
Section as
well as the
anonymous
reviewers for
this November
issue. Their
careful
reading and
evaluation of
the submitted
papers
enhanced the
quality of the
papers
published in
this
collection.
References
Alvarez A.A. (2014)
Cultural Diversity. In: ten Have H.
(eds) Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics.
Springer, Cham. CrossRef
Thorseth, M. (2006).
Worldwide deliberation and public use of
reason online. Ethics and information
Technology, 8(4), 243-252. CrossRef
Bohman, J. (1995). Public
reason and cultural pluralism: Political
liberalism and the problem of moral
conflict. Political Theory, 23, 253-279.
CrossRef