Etikk i praksis. Nordic Journal of Applied Ethics (2019),
13(1), 39-54 |
http://dx.doi.org/10.5324/eip.v13i1.2749 |
Energy Scenarios and Justice for Future Humans: An Application of the Capabilities Approach to the Case of Swedish Energy Politics
Anders Melin* & David Kronlid** *Department of Global Political Studies, Malmö University, anders.melin@mau.se **Department of Education, Uppsala University, david.kronlid@edu.uu.se
Energy
production and consumption give rise to
issues of justice for future humans. By
analysing a specific case – Swedish energy
politics – this article contributes to the
discussion of how consideration for future
humans should affect energy policy making.
It outlines three different energy scenarios
for the period 2035-2065 – the
nuclear-renewables, the renewables-low and
the renewables-high scenarios – and assesses
them from the point of view of justice for
future individuals by using the capabilities
approach as a normative framework. We cannot
make a definitive assessment of the
different scenarios due to the great
uncertainties involved in determining the
impacts on individuals living between 2035
and 2065 and individuals born thereafter,
but we still conclude that we have certain
reasons to prefer the renewables-low
scenario since it avoids certain risks
connected with the other scenarios. The
economic growth in this scenario is lower
than in the others, but we question whether
this is a disadvantage from the point of
view of the capabilities approach. Keywords:
energy scenarios,
justice, future generations, capabilities
approach
Though the use of energy is a pre-supposition for a modern life style, it also gives rise to issues of justice for future humans.1 All energy sources – nuclear energy, fossil fuels as well as renewables – have some possible negative impacts on the lives of future humans. There are strong moral reasons to consider these impacts, both from the points of view of Utilitarianism and of deontological theories (Thompson 2009, Tremmel 2014). The second purpose of this article is to contribute to the debate on how the capabilities approach can be applied to questions of justice to future humans, especially in the context of energy policy making. This approach is Martha Nussbaum’s version of an approach or theory that, in its more general form, can be denoted as the capability approach or capabilities theory (Robeyns 2016, Holland 2014). It has become increasingly influential as an approach to issues of social justice, such as questions concerning gender inequality (Walker, Berekashvili, Lomidze 2014), and recently it has been applied to issues concerning our responsibility towards future individuals (Watene 2013). Consequently, it is of great interest to examine how it can be used in the context of energy policy making. A few attempts have been made to apply the capabilities approach to the issue of energy policy making and justice, for example, by analysing how different capabilities are affected by limited access to energy and the negative environmental impacts of energy production (Day, Gordon, Simcock 2016, Hillerbrand 2015), but more research is needed . There are, of course, many other normative approaches that can be used for analysing issues of justice to future humans, but we do not have the space here for a more detailed discussion of their possible advantages and disadvantages. For the purpose of this article, it is enough to assume that the capabilities approach is one valuable approach and not necessarily preferable to all others (for a defence of capabilities as a unit for intergenerational distributive justice, see Page 2007A) . It should be noted that the aim of the article is to contribute to the ethical debate on how concern for future humans should affect energy policy making. We do not aim to contribute to the natural scientific, technological or economic debate, although we make use of results from such studies . We start by briefly describing the capabilities approach and how it can be applied to analysing issues of justice for future individuals. Thereafter, we analyse how the three energy scenarios should be assessed . The capabilities approach and issues of justice for future humans Capability is, of course, the key concept within the approach. It is defined in contrast to ‘functionings’, which refer to what people actually are or do, such as being workers or homemakers, or members of religious organizations. Functionings can be both complex and very elementary. Capability denotes the opportunity to choose a specific functioning. The emphasis on freedom of choice is connected with the fact that personal freedom concerning how one wants to live one’s life is regarded as a fundamental value within the capabilities approach. Consequently, the promotion of capabilities, rather than functioning, should be the goal of political decision making. For example, people should have the opportunity to have leisure time, but they should also be allowed to work sixteen hours a day if they so choose (Nussbaum 2013: 24-26, Nussbaum 2000: 87-88). From the point of view of the capabilities approach, it can be argued that we should also consider the capabilities of future humans. The duties that we have to other individuals are derived from their capabilities, which in turn are derived from their human dignity. In contrast to contractarian theories, such as Rawls’s theory of justice, social cooperation within the same society is not a requirement for having duties to others. Nussbaum claims that we have duties to humans in all parts of the world, based on what they need to live a dignified human life. Therefore, the capabilities approach should be applied globally, not just nationally. All the citizens of the world should be assigned the same entitlements, and these form the basis for the correlative duties that others have. All humans have an obligation to promote a dignified life for everyone, not only for fellow nationals (Nussbaum 2006: 273-280). If cooperation is not a requirement for deriving duties to people in other parts of the world, it seems inconsistent to regard it as a requirement when considering whether we have any duty to people living in the future. In accordance with Nussbaum’s capabilities approach, we also have reasons to assign to future humans certain entitlements that are necessary for living a dignified human life. The capabilities approach seems consistent with a principle of time neutrality, according to which we should not treat individuals differently just because of their position in time (Ekeli 2004: 429). Moreover, we should consider future humans in all parts of the world, since we cannot justify limiting our concern to current and future humans living in Sweden only. When applying the capabilities approach to questions of energy justice for future humans, we first need to establish a list of capabilities in order to analyse how current and future humans are affected by the production and consumption of energy. Nussbaum has put forward the following list of capabilities, of which each individual should be guaranteed a threshold level: 1) life, 2) bodily health, 3) bodily integrity (mobility), 4) senses, imagination, and thought, 5) emotions, 6) practical reason, 7) affiliation, 8) other species, 9) play, 10) control over one’s environment, both political and material (Nussbaum 2000: 74-81, Nussbaum 2013: 33-34). This extensive list seems relevant in an intragenerational context when comparing the impacts of a certain policy on different groups or individuals living now. However, when analysing the impacts on future humans, especially those living 50 years or more from now, we should acknowledge that the realization of capabilities by future humans is only partially dependent on the actions of current humans. Whether their capabilities are respected and promoted is to a large extent affected by the political decisions made during their lifetimes. For example, whether individuals born 50 years from now will realize the capability of senses, imagination or thought or not is only partly determined by decisions made by current humans. For example, if we emit a large amount of greenhouse gases so that individuals born in 50 years live in a world with a global mean temperature of 6℃ above the current mean, the frequency of drought and floods is likely to increase significantly. As a result, the increased temperature could lead to a notable decrease in human welfare and a weakening of social institutions, such as the educational system. However, the impact on the education of future humans is still only partly a consequence of the actions of current humans and is to a large extent influenced by future decisions. The actions of current humans will impact the environmental goods of future individuals to a large extent but their personal and social goods to a lesser extent, since these goods are more strongly influenced by future decisions. When analysing the capability deprivations of future humans, it is necessary to distinguish between deprivations caused mainly by current humans and those caused mainly by future humans themselves. It is primarily the former that are of interest in the context of justice to future humans. For that reason, our analysis needs to focus on the capabilities connected with material well-being, as they are more directly related to environmental goods. Moreover, since being able to freely choose one’s life is central to Nussbaum’s capabilities approach, and since this capability is also greatly influenced by the actions of current humans, we include the capability of practical reason in our analysis. Thus, our list encompasses the following capabilities: 1) life, 2) bodily health, 3) practical reason, and 4) control over one’s material environment. The capability to live with other species will also be strongly affected by different energy scenarios. However, we do not include it in our analysis, partly due to space limitations and partly since it is often argued that it is less important than many of the other capabilities (Okin 2003: 311). with Nussbaum’s intention that the capabilities approach should be understood as a minimal theory of justice (Nussbaum 2000: 75). Concerning the capability of life, we consider the threshold to be a length of life that is considerably lower than the current global average. Regarding bodily health, individuals are considered to be situated below the threshold only if they suffer from serious diseases. As for the capability of practical reasons, individuals are considered to be below it only if they have considerably fewer opportunities to decide how to live their lives than the average individual in today’s democratic societies. Concerning the capability of control over one’s environment, people are considered to be below it if their property, including land, is in very poor condition. In line with Nussbaum’s argumentation, a minimal requirement of justice is that current individuals should not cause or risk causing future individuals to be situated below the threshold value for any of the listed capabilities. However, since all energy scenarios risk leading to some significant negative impacts for future individuals, we have to make a choice between different scenarios that all entail a certain risk that individuals will be situated below the threshold at least for some of the capabilities on the list. The principle of sufficiency is central for the capability approach, but it can be interpreted in different ways. A moral radical interpretation of it would give sufficiency lexical priority over other principles. This means that increasing the number of individuals existing above the sufficiency threshold for all capabilities should be given priority over all other justice values, such as equality. For example, a situation A in which five individuals are far above the threshold levels for all capabilities and four individuals are very far below the threshold for all capabilities should be seen as preferable to a situation B in which four individuals are slightly above the threshold for all capabilities and five individuals are slightly below it for only one of the capabilities on the list. However, as the previous example shows, giving lexical priority to sufficiency seems to have outcomes that clearly conflict with common moral intuitions. A moderate interpretation of the principle of sufficiency that recognizes that equality may also be important seems preferable (Page 2007B:15, Arneson 2006: 28). Our guiding principle is therefore that we should choose the scenario that leads to the largest number of future humans existing above the threshold for all the capabilities on the list. However, if a scenario X leads to a slightly larger number of future humans existing above the threshold for all the capabilities on the list than a scenario Y, at the same time as scenario X leads to much greater inequalities among future humans, then scenario Y should be chosen. In addition, it seems unreasonable that a very small advantage for future individuals should be bought at the expense of very large burdens for current individuals. Thus, our starting point will be that a scenario C is preferable to a scenario D if C leads to a better outcome for future individuals, unless the difference between the two scenarios for future individuals is very small and D leads to a much better outcome for current individuals. Applying the capabilities approach to the case of Swedish energy politics When applying the capabilities approach to our case, we make use of earlier scientific studies of possible future energy scenarios for Sweden (IVA 2014, 2016A, 2016B, Energimyndigheten 2016, IEA 2016 and Gustavsson, Särnholm, Stigson, Zetterberg 2011). We also employ earlier scientific studies on historical and possible future impacts of different energy sources, as well as documents about such impacts from Swedish authorities (see below). We assume that that the Swedish government is going to decide which energy mix should be allowed and promoted between 2035 and 2065.2 Today, the consensus both within climate science and politics is that we need to phase out fossil fuels in order to limit global warming to 2℃ (McGlade & Elkins 2015: 187-190). To capture and bury CO2 is sometimes described as a possible solution for continuing to use fossil fuels and at the same time reducing GHG emissions. However, it is questionable whether technologies for carbon capture and storage are a realistic solution since they are both expensive and energy consuming and would require massive investments in the necessary infrastructure (Heinberg & Fridley 2016: 135-136). A significant use of fossil fuels will have considerable effects on the climate and will contribute to an increased frequency of drought, floods and cyclones in the future (IPCC 2014: 8). It is highly likely that scenarios including a significant use of fossil fuels will cause a larger number of future humans to be situated below the threshold for any of the capabilities than scenarios with only a limited use of fossil fuels, if the differences between the scenarios are small in other respects. Nuclear energy is another controversial energy technology, which is currently an important part of the Swedish energy mix. However, in contrast to fossil fuels, whether it should be phased out or not is a more contentious issue (Sovacool, Brown, Valentine 2016: 249-270). Given the arguments above, the following three scenarios seem to be the most preferable in terms of justice to future humans: 1) to phase out fossil fuels and replace them with renewables, and continue with nuclear energy, 2) to phase out both nuclear energy and fossil fuels, and replace them with renewables, or 3) to phase out both nuclear energy and fossil fuels as in the second scenario, but not to replace them with renewables to the same extent. Other scenarios are, of course, possible, but we choose to focus on these scenarios since they reflect two of the main choices Sweden will have to make: to continue with or phase out nuclear energy, and to continue with the current high level of energy consumption or to decrease it substantially. We label the first alternative ‘nuclear-renewables’, the second ‘renewables-high’ and the third ‘renewables-low’. These scenarios are inspired by the scenarios put forward in a report by the Swedish Energy Agency (Energimyndigheten 2016), but they are more similar to one another in order to facilitate a comparison. Sweden’s energy source distribution in 2014 serves as a baseline: fossil fuel 129 TWh, electricity 123 TWh, bioenergy 72 TWh and district heating 51 TWh. The total energy consumption came to 375 TWh (Energimyndigheten 2016). We assume that Sweden will have a similar social welfare system to today in all three scenarios. The scenarios build on the technologies available today, since it would be problematic to assume the existence and application of new forms of technology during the period 2035-2065. In the nuclear-renewables scenario, the total energy consumption in the year 2050 is 359 TWh (see the table below). The consumption of nuclear energy will remain relatively high, and wind and solar power will increase in comparison with today.3 The division between the different types of energy in the year 2050 is described below. The economic growth is on average 2% per year,4 but the total consumption of energy is lower than in the year 2014 because of higher energy efficiency. The amount of energy used to produce a certain amount of goods and services in 2050 is only 47% of what it was in 2014.5 In the renewables-high scenario, both nuclear energy and fossil fuels are phased out by the year 2050. In this scenario, the total energy production and consumption, the economic growth and the energy efficiency are the same as in the nuclear-renewables scenario. The use of nuclear energy in the latter scenario is replaced with an increased use of wind power, solar power and bioenergy.6 In the renewables-low scenario, the use of both nuclear energy and fossil fuels is phased out by the year 2050. In this scenario, the use of nuclear energy in the nuclear-renewables scenario is not replaced, which means that the total energy production and consumption is reduced by 60 TWh, to 299 TWh. The renewables-low scenario has less economic growth than the other three scenarios, approximately 1.5% per year on average, which means that the total levels of transportation and production are a little lower. The energy efficiency is the same as in the other scenarios. In both the renewables-high and renewables-low scenarios, biofuel gas-turbine power is used periodically as a solution to the problem of the intermittency of wind and solar power. Since we need to use biofuel both for producing electricity and for transportation,7 it is difficult to achieve a renewable energy scenario with less bioenergy consumption than 100 TWh by the year 2050, unless the amount of transportation decreases drastically.8 When assessing the different scenarios from the point of view of justice for future individuals, we need to predict how each scenario will affect both individuals living between 2035 and 2065 and individuals born after 2065 (hereafter labelled ‘future humans’). Because of the limited space here, we focus on the most significant impacts and differences between the scenarios. When comparing the nuclear-renewables scenario with the two others, its disadvantages include the risks connected with uranium mining, the disposal of additional nuclear waste and of a core melt-down. The impact of uranium mining leads to low-level, but long-lived, radioactive waste (Smith and others 2012: 295-296). However, so far it has only been established that uranium mining has negative health effects on workers in uranium mines, not on individuals living in the vicinity (Tomasek, Rogel, Tirmache, Mitton, Laurier 2008, Winde, Erasmus, Geipel 2017). Therefore, we cannot draw any conclusion as to whether uranium mining will cause a significant number of individuals living between 2035 and 2065 and a significant number of future humans to be situated below the threshold value for any of the capabilities on the list. However, the nuclear-renewables scenario seems to pose additional risks, due to the possibility of a core melt-down. If a core melt-down occurs between 2035 and 2065, the risk is high that it will significantly affect several thousand individuals living during that period, as has been the case with earlier core melt-downs, such as Chernobyl.9 There is a high risk that some individuals will be situated below the threshold value for one or several of the listed capabilities, primarily those of life and bodily health. In addition, the capabilities of individuals born after 2065 may be affected if they live in areas contaminated by radiation or are born to irradiated parents.10 However, a core melt-down is likely to primarily affect individuals living in the 2035-2065 period and only secondarily future humans. The likelihood of a core-melt down is a contested issue, which is very difficult to predict accurately. According to estimates based on Probabilistic Risk Assessment,11 the risk has been estimated to occur once in every 20 000 to 40 000 reactor years for Generation II reactors (the type of reactors used in Sweden today). If we instead base our estimates on historical data, the core damage frequency becomes considerably higher: according to some estimates as much as once in every 1300 reactor years (Taebi, Roeser, van de Poel 2012: 202-206).
The
degree
of risk that
nuclear waste
disposal may
lead to is
also a
controversial
issue. In
their
application
for permission
to construct a
final
repository for
nuclear waste,
SKB (Swedish
Nuclear Fuel
and Waste
Management
Company)
argues that
their proposed
method for
nuclear waste
disposal,
KBS-3, fulfils
the very
strict risk
criterion
established by
SSM (Swedish
Radiation
Safety
Authority),
which says
that the
yearly risk
for damage
after
enclosing the
nuclear waste
deposit should
be at most one
per million
for a
representative
individual in
the group
exposed to the
largest risk
(SKB 2011:
31-33).12
Given the current scientific debate, we cannot conclude that the risk of a core melt-down and the risk of the spread of disposed nuclear waste are negligible, although they both appear relatively low. Risks also exist in the renewables-high and the renewables-low scenarios connected with nuclear waste disposal, since we need to dispose of the nuclear waste produced before the phase-out of nuclear energy. However, since the amount of nuclear waste is larger in the nuclear-renewables scenario, the risk is higher. In addition to the risks of a nuclear melt-down and the increased risk of the spread of nuclear waste, a disadvantage of the nuclear-renewables scenario is that it requires considerable resources to decommission nuclear reactors. For that reason, nuclear energy is less reversible than bioenergy and renewables. It will have a negative effect on future individuals’ freedom of choice and therefore on their capability of practical reason (Hillerbrand & Peterson 2014: 586). However, given that Sweden will have a similar political system in the near future, individuals living at that point in time will still have the opportunity to exercise their freedom of choice in other areas of life. It is not likely that a significantly larger number of future humans will be situated below the threshold of practical reason in the nuclear-renewables scenario. The renewables-high scenario has certain disadvantages compared with the nuclear-renewables scenario. The main disadvantage is connected with the higher level of bioenergy production in this scenario. Estimates of greenhouse gas emissions from bioenergy production, regardless of whether it is based on dedicated biomass or waste treatment, are considerably higher than estimates of greenhouse gas emissions from solar power, wind power and nuclear energy (Kadiyala, Kommalapati, Huque 2016: 8, Amponsah, Troldborg, Kington, Aalders, Hough 2014: 463-469). Due to its effects on global warming, the higher bioenergy production and consumption in the renewables-high scenario risk leading to a higher number of individuals, both those living from 2035-2065 and future humans, being situated below the threshold for any of the capabilities. Producing more wind and solar power also requires greater amounts of rare earth elements (REE), the mining of which leads to large negative environmental impacts (Paul & Campbell 2011: 14). However, so far it has not been shown that REE mining has considerable negative effects on individuals living close to those mining areas (Zhu and others 2005, Hao and others 2015). In addition, the higher use of REE means that fewer resources will be left for current and future humans, but determining how much they will be affected is difficult. It is thus uncertain whether the higher use of REE in the renewables-high scenario will cause a significant number of individuals living from 2035-2065 or future humans to be situated below the threshold for any of the capabilities. An additional disadvantage with the renewables-high scenario is that the increase in wind and solar power requires more land use. The low-energy density of these energy sources is often described as problematic (Hillerbrand 2015: 246). However, since Sweden is a sparsely populated country, it is not likely that the land use connected with a moderate expansion of wind and solar power will cause a significant number of people living in the 2035-2065 period or future humans to be situated below the threshold for any of the capabilities. As seen above, uncertainties connected with determining the likely consequences for future humans of the two scenarios abound, making it difficult to conclude which of these is preferable. We cannot say whether the higher wind, solar and bioenergy power production and consumption in the renewables-high scenario are likely to cause more individuals living from 2035-2065 or future humans to be situated below the threshold for any of the capabilities than the nuclear energy production in the nuclear-renewables scenario. Moreover, we do not have any reason to expect that one of the scenarios will lead to considerably larger inequalities among future humans than the other. To conclude, we do not have any strong reason to prefer one of the scenarios from the perspective of justice to future humans. The renewables-low scenario does have certain advantages compared with both the other scenarios. In contrast to the nuclear-renewables scenario, the renewables-low scenario avoids the risks connected with a core melt-down and the disposal of additional nuclear waste. In comparison with the renewables-high scenario, it avoids the impacts of additional use of bioenergy and additional production of wind and solar power, although the latter can be expected to have fewer negative consequences. A potential disadvantage in the renewables-low scenario is the lower production of goods and services, but it can be questioned whether this is really a disadvantage from the capabilities approach point of view. According to what has traditionally been the dominant view within economics, higher economic growth leads to increased welfare for both current and future humans. Current individuals will be able to consume more goods and services and future humans will also benefit, since a higher level of economic growth leaves more human-made capital to future humans, as well as more advanced technologies to manage environmental problems. However, the capabilities approach questions the traditional view of social development within economics. For example, Nussbaum argues that GNP per capita is misleading as a measurement for social development since it ignores questions about the distribution of wealth and income. Moreover, important goods, such as life expectancy, are not always well correlated with wealth and income (Nussbaum 2000:60-61). Since the capabilities approach is primarily concerned with helping individuals reach the threshold level, increased economic growth is of limited value unless it improves the situation for individuals situated below the threshold. In addition, many of today’s economists are sceptical of whether increased economic growth necessarily benefits current and future humans, partly due to increasing recognition of the negative environmental effects of higher production and consumption. Some claim that it would be preferable for humanity as a whole if developed countries slowed down their rate of growth, or even decreased their production of goods and services (Abramovay 2016, Daly 2014, Kallis, Demaria, D’Alisa 2015). In this particular case, it seems uncertain whether the lower economic growth in the renewables-low scenario would cause a higher or lower number of future humans to be situated below the threshold for any of the capabilities. It is likely that in the renewables-low scenario, we will have less human-made capital and fewer advanced technologies after 2065, but the overall consequences for future humans are not necessarily negative since lower production and consumption during the period 2035-2065 would also mean less depletion of natural resources. On a global level, it may very well be the case that a smaller number of future humans will be under the threshold for any of the capabilities, due to the lower economic growth in Sweden during this period. The lower economic growth in the renewables-low scenario could be a disadvantage if it is likely to lead to a considerably higher number of individuals living between 2035-2065 being situated below the threshold, even if the likelihood of a higher number of future humans being situated below the threshold is unclear. However, we do not have strong reasons to expect that this scenario would have such consequences. As for Swedish citizens, the fact that Sweden already is an affluent country with a strong welfare system means that lower economic growth does not necessarily lead to a larger number of individuals ending up below the threshold level for any of the capabilities. The social welfare system would provide for many of the individuals with limited means so that they would still reach the minimum threshold level. As for individuals living in other parts of the world, the consequences are considerably less certain. Lower consumption in Sweden may mean lower incomes for citizens in other countries, but how much lower and how much they will be affected is unclear. At the same time, the lower production and consumption of resources in Sweden may lead to fewer negative environmental effects for individuals in other parts of the world. To conclude, the case study clearly shows the difficulties involved in making an assessment of different scenarios from the point of view of justice to future humans. Due to the great uncertainties about the possible impacts on humans living between 2035 and 2065 and on future humans, we cannot make a definitive assessment of the three scenarios based on justice to future humans. However, we still have certain reasons to prefer the renewables-low scenario. It avoids the risks connected with nuclear energy production in the nuclear-renewables scenarios and the higher production of bioenergy, wind and solar power in the renewables-high scenario. At the same time, it is uncertain whether the lower production and consumption of goods and services in this scenario would lead to a larger or smaller number of individuals being below the threshold for any of the capabilities in either of the timeframes considered. In addition, we do not have any reason to expect that the renewables-low scenario will lead to significantly larger inequalities between future humans than the other scenarios. Conclusion In this article, we discuss how the capabilities approach can be applied to issues of justice to future humans, especially in the context of energy policy making. We conclude that within the framework of the approach, we have reason to assign capabilities to future humans based on their human dignity. Because future humans’ realization of some capabilities on Nussbaum’s list will primarily be a consequence of decisions made after they have been born rather than of the actions of current humans, we suggest a shorter version of the capabilities list for analysing issues of justice to future humans: 1) life, 2) bodily health, 3) practical reason and 4) control over one’s environment. We apply the capabilities approach to three different scenarios for Swedish energy politics for the period 2035-2065: the nuclear-renewables, the renewables-high and the renewables-low scenarios. We cannot reach a definitive conclusion because of the uncertainties connected with predicting the consequences of the scenarios, but we still have certain reasons to prefer the renewables-low scenario. This scenario, in comparison with the nuclear-renewables scenario, avoids the risks of nuclear energy production and of managing additional nuclear waste during the period 2035-2065. Compared with the renewables-high scenario, the renewables-low scenario avoids the risks of additional bioenergy use and increased production of wind and solar power. The economic growth is lower in the renewables-low scenario, but it is uncertain whether that would lead to a higher or lower number of current and future humans being situated below the threshold for any of the capabilities. From the point of view of the capabilities approach, we need to question whether higher energy production with concomitant higher economic growth in a developed country is always preferable. However, we would have stronger reasons to prefer a scenario with higher energy production in a developing country, in which a large number of today’s individuals find. Acknowledgements This article has been written as a part of the research project “Energy and justice – an ethical analysis of Swedish energy politics based on the capability approach”, Dnr 421-2013-781, funded by the Swedish Research Council (Vetenskapsrådet). Notes 1
We use the term ‘future humans’
rather than ‘future generations’ since it is
problematic to claim that we have duties to
generations as collective entities over and
above the duties we have to the individuals
constituting the generations. Such a
claim presupposes that generations can have
morally relevant interests that differ from the
interests of the individuals constituting the
generations. Moreover, the focus on individuals
is also in line with Nussbaum’s capabilities
approach since she argues that capabilities
should primarily be ascribed to individuals, not
groups (see Nussbaum 2013: 35). 2 What can be considered feasible
after that period of time is difficult to
predict because of possible future innovations
in the area of energy technology. Moreover, a
more sudden change of the current energy mix,
for example by phasing-out nuclear energy by the
year 2025, will be very expensive and will make
it necessary to import electricity produced by
fossil fuel plants (see IVA 2016:14 and Qvist
& Brook 2015: 1-10). How energy
is produced is, of course, also determined by
market decisions and not only by political
decisions; but political decisions still
determine the framework within which market
decisions are made. 3 An expansion of wind power is
economically realistic since it has become
relatively cheap and is expected to become even
cheaper in the future, see (Nohlgren, Herstad
Svärd, Jansson, Rodin 2014). The cost of solar
power is also decreasing, see (MIT 2015). 4 This is the same average economic
growth as Sweden has had since the 1970s (the
webpage of Statistics Sweden, accessed
2019-01-03). 5 According to estimates by the Royal
Swedish Academy of Engineering Sciences (IVA),
significantly increased energy efficiency in
Sweden is both technologically and economically
feasible (IVA 2014). It is also in line with the
dominant political goals. In November 2016, the
government made an agreement together with the
New Moderates, the Centre Party and the
Christian Democrats that Sweden will have 50%
more efficient energy use in 2030, compared to
2005 (the webpage of the Swedish government,
http://www.regeringen.se, accessed 2017-08-03). 6 Such an increase of wind and solar
energy seems realistic, although it requires
investments in technology for storing energy.
According to estimates by the Royal Swedish
Academy of Engineering Sciences, in Sweden
land-based wind energy has a potential of 160
TWh and solar energy a potential of 50 TWh (IVA
2016A, IVA 2016B). According to several
prognoses, a long-term phase-out of Swedish
nuclear energy is technically and economically
feasible. For example, a study from the
International Energy Agency states that nuclear
energy in Sweden can be completely phased-out
before 2040, International Energy Agency (2016):
Nordic
Energy Technology Perspectives 2016: Cities,
flexibility and pathways to carbon-neutrality,
Paris. 7 A total replacement of fossil
fuels with electricity within the transport
sector does not seem likely in the near future
(Heinberg & Fridley: 81-94, Gustavsson and
others 2011: 33). 8 In the study by the Swedish
Energy Agency, the bioenergy consumption is 100
TWh in the scenario with the lowest bioenergy
consumption (Energimyndigheten 2016). Moreover,
in another study of the future Swedish bioenergy
consumption, it is estimated to be between
165-248 TWh in 2050 (Gode, Särnholm, Zetterberg,
Arnell, Zetterberg 2010:55). 9 A WHO report, based on earlier
scientific studies, estimates the number of
premature deaths due to the Chernobyl accident
to be in the magnitude of several thousand.
According to the report, there is no doubt that
it has led to significantly higher rates of
thyroid cancer among the population in the most
heavily contaminated areas. However, there is no
convincing evidence that it has led to increased
risk of other cancer forms, such as leukaemia
(Bennet, Repacholi, Zhanat 2006:2, 53, 60 and
64). 10
There is a high risk that a major core
melt-down will also affect future individuals.
As for Chernobyl, children born after the
accident in the areas contaminated by radiation,
or children born in non-contaminated areas but
by irradiated parents, had an increased
frequency of genome damage, which is associated
with higher risk of cancer, see (Fucic,
Aghajanyan, Druzhinin, Minina, Neronova 2016). 11 Probabilistic Risk Assessment
consisting in identifying the event that could
lead to an accident and assigning probabilities
to them. References
Abramovay, R. (2016). Beyond the Green Economy. London and New York: Routledge.
Amponsah, N.Y., Troldborg, M., Kington, B., Aalders, I., Hough, R. L. (2014). Greenhouse gas emissions from renewable energy sources: A review of lifecycle considerations. Renewable and Sustainable Energy Reviews, 39: 461-475. CrossRef
Anshelm, J. (2000). Mellan
frälsning och domedag: Om kärnkraftens
politiska idéhistoria i Sverige 1945-1999.
Eslöv, Symposion
Arneson, R. (2006). Distributive justice and basic capability equality: “Good enough” is not good enough. In Kaufman, A. (Ed.), Capabilities Equality: Basic Issues and Problems, (pp. 17-43). New York, London: Routledge
Bennet, B., Repacholi, M., Zhanat, C. (Eds.) (2006). Health Effects of the Chernobyl Accident and Special Health Care Programmes: Report of the UN Chernobyl Forum Expert Group “Health”. Geneva: WHO. Daly, H. (2014): From Uneconomic Growth to a Steady-State Economy. Cheltenham, UK and Northampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar. CrossRef
Day, R., Walker, G., Simcock, N. (2016). Conceptualising energy use and energy poverty using a capabilities framework. Energy Policy, 93: 255-264. CrossRef
Ekeli, K. S. (2004). Environmental Risks, Uncertainty and Intergenerational Ethics. Environmental Values, 13 (4): 421-448. CrossRef Energimyndigheten (the Swedish Energy Agency) (2016) Fyra framtider: Energisystemet efter 2020 (Four Futures: The Swedish energy system beyond 2020). Stockholm: Energimyndigheten.
Fucic, A., Aghajanyan, A., Druzhinin, V., Minina, V., Neronova, E. (2016). Review article: Follow-up studies on genome damage in children after Chernobyl nuclear power plant accident. Archives of Toxicology, 90: 2147-2159. CrossRef
Gode,
J.,
Särnholm, E., Zetterberg, L.,
Arnell, J., Zetterberg, T.
(2010). Swedish
long-term low carbon scenario:
Exploratory study on
opportunities and barriers,
Stockholm: Swedish Environmental
Research Institute
Gustavsson, M., Särnholm,
E., Stigson, P., Zetterberg, L.
(2011). Energy
scenarios for Sweden 2050 Based on
Renewable Energy Technologies and
Sources. IVL Swedish
Environment Institute and WWF
Sweden, Göteborg and Stockholm
Hao,
Z.,
Li, Y., Li, H., Wei, B., Liao,
X., Liang, T., Yu, J. (2015).
Levels of rare earth elements,
heavy metals and uranium in a
population living in Baiyun Obo,
Inner Mongolia, China: A pilot
study. Chemosphere,
128: 161-170.
CrossRef.
Heinberg, R., Fridley, D. (2016). Our Renewable Future: Laying the Path for One Hundred Percent Clean Energy. Washington, D.C: Island Press. CrossRef
Hillerbrand, R. (2015). The role of nuclear energy in the future energy landscape. In Taebi, B. and Roeser, S. (Eds.), The Ethics of Nuclear Energy: Risk, Justice, and Democracy in the post-Fukushima Era, (pp. 231-249). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press Hillerbrand, R., Peterson, M. (2014). Nuclear Power is Neither Right nor Wrong: The Case for a Tertium Datur in the Ethics of Technology. Science & Engineering Ethics, 20 (2): 583-595, http://dx.doi.org./10.1007/s11948-013-9452-5
Holland, B. (2014). Allocating the Earth: A Distributional Framework for Protecting Capabilities in Environmental Law and Policy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. . CrossRef IEA (International Energy Agency) (2016): Nordic Energy Technology Perspectives 2016: Cities,flexibility and pathways to carbon-neutrality, Paris
IPCC
(2014),
Climate
Change 2014, Synthesis
Report: Summary for
Policymakers
IVA
(Kungl.
Ingenjörsvetenskapsakademien
[The Royal Swedish Academy
of Engineering Science]) (2014) 50 procent
effektivare
energianvändning 2050.
Slutrapport från IVAs
projekt Ett
energieffektivt samhälle.
Stockholm
IVA (Kungl.
Ingenjörsvetenskapsakademien)
(2016A). Fem vägval för
Sverige. Syntesrapport.
Stockholm
IVA (Kungl.
Ingenjörsvetenskapsakademien)
(2016B). Framtidens el –
så påverkas klimat och
miljö. En
delrapport.
Stockholm
Kadiyala,
A.,
Kommalapati, R., Huque, Z.
(2016). Quantification of
the Lifecycle Greenhouse
Gas Emissions from Nuclear
Power Generation Systems.
Energies, 9 (11):1-13. CrossRef
Kallis, G., Demaria, F.,
D’Alisa, G. (Eds.)
(2015). Degrowth:
A
Vocabulary for A New Era.
Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge
McGlade, C., Elkins, P. (2015) The geographical distribution of fossil fuels unused when limiting global warming to 2 ℃. Nature, 517: 187-190. CrossRef
Mark- och
miljödomstolen (2018) Sammanfattning av yttrande, Mål
nr M 1333-11
Major, B., Cozzarelli, C. & Cooper, M. (2000) Psychological Responses of Women After First-Trimester Abortion. Archives of General Psychiatry 57(8): 777-784. CrossRef MIT (2015). The Future of Solar Energy: An Interdisciplinary MIT Study. Cambridge: MA
MKG
(2012).
Comments
on plans for the final disposal
of spent nuclear fuel. Göteborg Nohlgren, I., Herstad Svärd, S., Jansson, M., Rodin, J. (2014). El från nya och framtida anläggningar 2014 (Elforsk rapport 14:40). Stockholm
Nussbaum,
M.
C. (2000). Women
and Human Development: The
Capabilities Approach.
Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. CrossRef Nussbaum, M. C. (2006). Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press Okin,
S.
M. (2003). Poverty,
Well-Being and
Gender: What Counts,
Who’s Heard? Philosophy
& Public
Affairs, 31
(3): 280-316.
CrossRef
Page,
E.
A. (2007A).
Intergenerational
justice of what:
Welfare, resources
or capabilities? Environmental Politics, 16 (3):
453-469. CrossRef
Page,
E.
A. (2007B).
Justice Between
Generations:
Investigating a
Sufficientarian
Approach. Journal
of Global
Ethics, 3
(1) 3-20. CrossRef
Paltsev,
S.
(2017). Energy
scenarios: the
value and
limits of
scenario
analysis.
WIREs Energy
and
Environment.
6: 1-19,
http://dx.doi.org./10.1002/
wene.242
Paul, J., Campbell, G. (2011). Investigating Rare Earth Element Mine Development in EPA Region8 and Potential Environmental Impacts, EPA Document-908R11003. Environmental Protection Agency, Washington, D.C
Qvist,
S.
A., Brook, B. W. (2015).
Environmental and health impacts
of a policy to phase out nuclear
power in Sweden. Energy
Policy, 84: 1-10 CrossRef
Robeyns,
I.
(2016). Capabilitarianism. Journal
of Human Development and
Capabilities, 17 (3): 397-414.
CrossRef Schröder,
J.
(2016). Geological Disposal of
Radioactive Waste: A Long-Term
Socio-Technical Experiment. Science
and Engineering Ethics, 22:
687-705. CrossRef
SKB (2011) Ansökan
om tillstånd enligt lagen (1984:3)
om
kärnteknisk verksamhet till
uppförande, innehav och drift
av en kärnteknisk anläggning
för slutförvaring av använt
kärnbränsle och kärnavfall
Sovacool,
B.
K., Brown, M. A., Valentine, S.
V. (2016). Fact and Fiction in
Global Energy Policy: 15
Contentious Questions.
Baltimore, MY: John Hopkins
University Press
Smith,
K.
R., Balakrishnan, K., Butler,
Colin, C., Zoë, Fairlie, I.,
Kinney, P., …Wilkinson, P.
(2012). Energy and Health. In
Johansson, T. B., Patwardhan,
A., Nakcenovic, N.,
Gomez-Echeverri, L. (Eds.), Global Energy Assessment, (pp.
255-324), Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press
Statistics
Sweden
(Statistiska centralbyrån),
https://www.scb.se/hittastatistik/
artiklar/2017/Unik-tillvaxt-nar-Sverige-gick-fran-jordbruk-till-tjanster/ , accessed
2019-01-03
Swedish
Government,
http://www.regeringen.se,
accessed 2017-08-03
Taebi, B., Roeser, S.,
van de Poel, I. (2012). The
ethics of nuclear power: Social
experiments, intergenerational
justice, and emotions. Energy
Policy, 51: 202-206.
CrossRef
Thompson,
J.
(2009). Intergenerational
Justice: Rights and
Responsibilities in an
Intergenerational Polity. New
York: Routledge
Tomasek,
L.,
Rogel, A., Tirmache, M.,
Mitton, N., Laurier, D.
(2008). Lung Cancer in French
and Czech Uranium Miners:
Radon-Associated Risk at Low
Exposure Rates and Modifying
Effects of Time since Exposure
and Age at Exposure. Radiation
Research, 169 (2):
125-137. CrossRef
Tremmel,
J.
C. (2014). A Theory of Intergenerational Justice.
Routledge: New
York
Walker,
J.,
Berekashvili, N., Lomidze, N.
(2014). Valuing Time: Time Use
Survey, the Capability Approach, and
Gender Analysis. Journal
of
Human Development and Capabilities,
15 (1): 47-59. CrossRef
Watene,
K.
(2013). Nussbaum’s Capability
Approach and Future Generations. Journal
of Human Development and
Capabilities, 14 (1): 21-39.
CrossRef
Winde, F., Erasmus,
E., Geipel, G. (2017). Uranium
contaminated drinking water
linked to leukaemia – Revisiting
a case study from South Africa
taking alternative exposure
pathways into account. Science
of
Total Environment, 574:
400-421. CrossRef
Zhu, W., Xu, S., Shao, P., Zhang, H., Wu, D., Yang, W., …Feng, L. (2005). Investigation on liver function among population in high background of rare earth area in South China. Biological Trace Element Research, 104 (1): 1-8. CrossRef
|